Category Archives: Uncategorized

Aspects of a Theory of Syntax and Behaviourism

                          Introduction

In this paper the competence-performance distinction first proposed by Chomsky (1965) will be analysed in relation to behavioural science. The paper will consider three primary criticisms of behaviourism from the point of view of the competence performance distinction: (1) behaviourists decision to stick with describing speech patterns and habits prevent them from constructing a credible theory of performance (Chomsky 1965), (2) Behaviourists methodology of only dealing with performance and eschewing explanations in terms of competence precludes them from being a serious science (Collins 2007), (3) Behaviourists don’t engage in idealisations and are committed to counting every cough in an instance of verbal behaviour and hence reduce their science to triviality (Jackendoff 2002). It will be demonstrated by considering developments in behavioural science that these criticisms are not justified. To illustrate the point, I will discuss explanations in both behavioural psychology (as exemplified by relational frame theory), and behaviourism in philosophy as exemplified by Quine. These examples will illustrate behaviourists appealing to underlying competencies to explain behaviour as well as using idealizations.

The fact that behavioural scientists use idealizations and appeal to competencies, doesn’t tell us much about the truth of their overall theories. But for interdisciplinary interaction between behaviourists and cognitivists to be fruitful; it is necessary that they understand each other positions. To that end it is imperative that the behaviourist position in the competence-performance distinction is explicated in detail.

Chomsky on the Competence and Performance Distinction

Sixty years ago, in his ‘Aspects of a Theory of Syntax’, Chomsky first explicitly made his distinction between competence and performance. In Aspects he is clear that he is not arguing against the study of performance as a field. Rather he is claiming that if one wants to study performance, then one will need to do so armed with an understanding of underlying competence mechanisms (Chomsky 1965 p.10). When discussing competence and performance Chomsky makes a distinction between acceptability judgements made by subjects and the actual grammaticalness of sentences. He argues that acceptability judgements are performance data which can be explained by underlying competence mechanisms (Ibid p. 11).

            He goes on to state that the following factors lead to unacceptability judgements; Repeated nesting, self-embedding, nesting of a long and complex element etc (Ibid p. 13). And he explains the unacceptability of, for example, repeated nesting, in terms of the finiteness of our memory (Ibid p. 14). Chomsky notes that people have been critical of generative grammar because of its focus on competence and lack of interest in performance. But he claims that the only research into performance that has had any theoretical interest, has been research that has been led by insights from underlying competence systems (Ibid p. 15). He went on to criticize descriptivist and classification philosophies as standing in the way of developing an adequate theory of performance:

“It is the descriptivist limitation-in-principle to classification and organization of data, to “extracting patterns” from a corpus of observed speech, to describing “speech habits” or “habit structures,” insofar as these may exist, etc., that precludes the development of a theory of actual performance.” (Ibid p. 15)

Chomsky doesn’t specify which theorists argue in this methodologically errant manner; but it will be demonstrated that his criticisms don’t apply to behaviourists in either psychology or philosophy.

Competence and Performance and Behaviourism

In this section I will look at the competence/performance issue from the point of view of behavioural science. I will argue that contemporary behavioural science cannot be described in terms of looking for “habit structures” or extracting patterns from the classification or organisation of data. Rather, behavioural science is discovering facts about the emergence of linguistic usage in the context of tightly controlled experimental settings. These discoveries in behavioural science such as (1) Rule-Governed Behaviour’s interaction with the contingencies of reinforcement, (2) the emergence of stimulus equivalence, (3) The emergence of relational frames, are experimentally controlled emergent properties of linguistic behaviour. Their discovery goes beyond mere “description” or “extracting of data from patterns”. Furthermore, there is no reason to think that such emergent species-specific performance data is explicable in terms of “habit structures”.

            While the performance data discovered in behavioural science cannot be reduced to “description”, or “extraction of data”, or explained in terms of “habit structures”, behavioural scientists haven’t provided much by way of an explanation of how these capacities emerge. The reason that such an explanation is wanting is because of an uncritical reliance on Skinner’s crude pragmatist philosophy. However, pace Skinner, any attempt to explain emergent behavioural capacities will be reliant on a distinction between the emergent behaviours and the underlying capacities which make the behaviours possible. Any cogent explanation of emergent behaviours will rely on behavioural science adapting a distinction between competence and performance analogous to that recommended by Chomsky (1965). We will see later that some behaviourists are already moving in this direction when we discuss Hayes and Sanford 2014 later in the paper.

Theorists have long critiqued behaviourists for failing to adequately account for the distinction between competence and performance. For example, philosopher John Collins has argued that behaviourism is not a serious discipline because it doesn’t even try to explain the underlying capacities responsible for behaviour (Collins 2007 p. 883). Arguing further that a focus on competence doesn’t involve ignoring performance; rather it involves explaining performance, through explicating the mechanisms underlying linguistic competence (Ibid p. 883).

            Collins’s claim that behaviourism is not a serious discipline is problematic. Experimental work in behaviourism over the last hundred or so years has yielded a wide range of experimental results which wouldn’t have been possible without research into behavioural science. The discovery of classical conditioning, and operant conditioning has revolutionized both psychology and biology. Since Chomsky wrote his ‘Aspects of a Theory of Syntax’ 60 years ago the field of behaviourism has continued to flourish demonstrating that it is a serious discipline which has made considerable advances over the last 60 years. Some discoveries in behavioural science of note have been Robert Rescorla’s discoveries of predictive mechanisms underlying classical conditioning (Rescorla 1969), the use of these predictive mechanisms to explain taste aversion in rats (Hayes & Sanford 2014), experimental literature demonstrating contingency insensitivity in rule following creatures (Galizio 1979, Shimoff et al 1981, Skinner 1984), the discovery of emergent stimulus equivalence (Sidman 1971), the discovery of emergent relational frames (Hayes & Thompson 1989)  (Hayes 2001).

            Even Skinner’s much maligned book ‘Verbal Behaviour’ has spawned hundreds of experiments on human subjects which have demonstrated some experimental control over his seven verbal operants (Sauter & Leblanc 2006). Likewise, behavioural science has demonstrated its use in applied disciplines, such as Applied Behavioural Analysis. So, any claim that behaviourism isn’t a serious discipline is conclusively refuted by the incredible predictive control it gives us over certain domains of interest.

            Nonetheless, Collins does have a point. There is a reluctance of some in behavioural science to provide explanations of the behavioural patterns in terms of underlying competencies some of which may be innate. This reluctance doesn’t demonstrate that behaviourism isn’t a serious discipline, but it does pose serious limitations on the explanatory capacity of the discipline to account for the discoveries they make. Later in the paper I will explore some recent tentative attempts to explain competencies underlying our capacity to relation frame. I will argue that these competencies demonstrate that these tentative steps are a step in the right direction in bridging the gap between behavioural science and cognitive science.

                What is Linguistic Competence?

            When discussing Chomsky’s distinction between competence and performance it is typical to justify the distinction in terms of idealizations which usually occur in any discipline. When Chomsky is talking about linguistic competence, he notes that he is doing so using a series of idealizations which are necessary to understand the complex object under study:

“Linguistic theory is concerned primarily with an ideal speaker listener, in a completely homogeneous speech-community, who knows its language perfectly and is unaffected by such grammatically irrelevant conditions as memory limitations, distractions, shifts of attention and interest, and errors (random or characteristic) in applying his knowledge of the language in actual performance.” (Chomsky 1965 p. 3)[1]

A grammar will then be a description of the rules the idealized subject is using when understanding or speaking their sentences (Ibid p.4). Chomsky’s notion of an idealized subject’s competence is analogous to the idealizations which physicists use all the time to gain traction over the physical phenomena they are studying. A cliched example is of a physicist using idealizations such as studying a frictionless plane to give them an understanding of force and energy (Jackendoff 2002 p. 33).

            Chomsky’s distinction between competence and performance which relies on idealizations is a sensible proposal and one which has led to success in gaining traction on the nature of language. While the use of idealizations is justified and common practice in science; Chomsky’s use of idealizations has had its critics. While most theorists would agree that some level of idealizations are needed it has been argued persuasively that Chomsky’s use of idealizations and his competence/performance distinction has ossified in such a manner as to make aspects of his theories irrefutable:

“Still, one can make a distinction between “soft” and “hard” idealizations. A “soft” idealization is acknowledged to be a matter of convenience, and one hopes eventually to find a natural way to re-integrate the excluded matters. A standard example is the friction of a frictionless plane in physics, which yields important generalizations about forces and energy. But one aspires eventually go beyond the idealization and integrate friction into the picture. By contrast, a “hard” idealization denies the need to go beyond itself; in the end it cuts itself off from the possibility of integration into a larger context…It is my unfortunate impression that, over the years, Chomsky’s articulation of the competence-performance distinction has moved from relatively soft…to considerably harder.” (Jackendoff 2002p. 33)

Other theorists have made similar points (Lakoff, G. 1987 p. 181, Palmer, D.  2023 p. 528).

Jackendoff isn’t arguing that we shouldn’t use idealizations or a competence-performance distinct rather he is warning of the possibility of an idealizing assumption becoming so hardened that it shields a theory from considering alternative ways of dealing with the data of experience. Thus, as we saw above Chomsky championed ignoring things like memory limitations, shifts of attention etc. But other work which doesn’t make this idealization actually use memory limitations to explain the hierarchical embedding in our language (Christiansen and Chater 2023, Christiansen and Chater 2016). Likewise, speech errors which Chomsky tells us to ignore in the name idealization have been used as productive data in explaining the cognitive processes underlying speech production (Hofstadter et al. 1989, Wijnen, F., 1992). Nonetheless, even Chomsky’s sternest critics would admit that his appeals to idealizations and the competence performance distinction have yielded interesting linguistic generalizations.

Jackendoff argued that the need for Chomsky to make the distinction between competence and performance was that other disciplines had failed to make the distinction:

“Chomsky makes the competence-performance distinction in part to ward off alternative proposals for how linguistics must be studied. In particular, he is justifiably resisting the behaviourists, who insisted that proper science requires counting every cough in the middle of a sentence as part of linguistic behaviour.” (Jackendoff 2002 p. 30).

While it is undeniable that behavioural science has a difficulty in explaining its own data because they do not always explain behaviour in terms of underlying competencies, nonetheless, Jackendoff in the above quote is engaging in a wild caricature of behaviourism.

            Some behaviourists do obviously argue that that the subject matter they are interested in are actual instances of behaviour in a particular context (Palmer, D., 2023 p. 528). And in criticisms of Chomsky’s conceptions of linguistics they do argue that as behaviourists they are not obliged to explain possible sentences created by linguists which conform to the purported grammatical principles but never used in actual verbal behaviour. If speakers do not actually use such verbal forms while behaving in relation to each other the behaviourist considers it beyond their purview to explain them (Ibid, p. 529). But whatever one thinks of this behaviourist philosophy; it doesn’t entail the extremes that Jackendoff attributes to it. 

            Jackendoff attributes to behaviourists the view that scientists should “count every cough in the middle of a sentences as part of linguistic behaviour”.  This claim amounts to the assertion that behaviourists do not think that scientists should use idealizations. This is an absurd accusation; any science which deprived itself of idealizations would be overwhelmed with complexity and wouldn’t be able get off the ground. It is simplifying idealizations which makes it possible for a scientific theory to gain any prediction and control.

            But contrary to Jackendoff’s wild claim behavioural science was from the start engaging in idealizations. Studying Classical and Operant Conditioning in a laboratory setting was an idealization which assumed that these artificial experiments could explain the complex learning processes of animals in the wild. Furthermore, in his Verbal Behaviour Skinner used a variety of idealizations. Skinner divided language into seven main verbal operants and treated them separately and under different types of stimulus control. But he noted that this was an idealizing assumption and that in practice the verbal operants would be intertwined and could be acquired together (Skinner 1957 p. 188).

 Furthermore, the notion of an operant was concerned with kinds of behaviour, that shared an effect on the environment and that, as a kind, are demonstrated to vary lawfully in their relations to other variables (Smith 1987 p. 289). Importantly, in his ‘Behaviourism and Logical Positivism’ Smith noted:

“The actual movements involved in pressing a lever, for example, might vary from instance to instance (e.g., left paw, right paw, nose), but they are equivalent with respect to producing reinforcement and they demonstrably function together in the face of changing conditions.” (ibid p. 289)

So even in the case of the operant itself idealisations are being used which results on the focus being on classes of behaviour[2]; so Jackendoff’s notion that behaviourists are engaging in “counting every cough” is simply absurd. Behavioural science like any other science is up to its eyes in idealizations from the start.

            Nonetheless, while Jackendoff is incorrect in his assertion that behaviourists don’t use idealizations he is correct that behaviourists have sometimes eschewed using the notion of competence in their explications of language. And this lack of a theory of competence does hinder their ability to explain the behavioural data which they have discovered.

         Behaviourists and Competence

Behaviourists by definition are concerned with behaviour. Hence, when Skinner wrote on language, he parsed this as the study of Verbal Behaviour. He divided language up into seven main verbal operants recommended empirically studying how various schedules of reinforcement maintained the use of these Verbal Operants. While he justified this research program in terms of studies which had been done on non-human animals; in the 70 years since Verbal Behaviour was written there has been hundreds of experimental studies on conditions responsible for maintaining the use of these Verbal Operants. Skinner’s theory is a paradigm case of an attempted explanation of human linguistic performance.

            Subsequent Behaviourist Research has moved beyond Skinner’s claims about language, e.g. Galizio (1979), Sidman (1971), Hayes & Thompson (1989) and Hayes (2001). But they still focus on behaviour and the degree to which it can be predicted and controlled using conditioning. Much behavioural science has had a heavy emphasis on practical predictive control to aid in applied work. Thus, the Verbal Behaviour Approach inspired by Skinner is heavily involved in teaching functional communication to people with severe autism and or an Intellectual disability. Sidman’s work on Stimulus Equivalence sprung out of his work trying to teach people with an intellectual disability how to read. While relational frame theory is used in attempts to teach people with intellectual disabilities functional communication, as well as a tool in Acceptance Commitment Therapy. This emphasis on applied work is sometimes used as a justification for a heavy emphasis on prediction and control (Dymond & Roche pp. 220-221). From a philosophical point of view, this emphasis on prediction and control is justified by appeal to a pragmatic philosophy of the type espoused by Steven Pepper (1942).

            This emphasis on pragmatic prediction and control of the organism clearly lays heavy weight on performance data; and the histories of reinforcement which shape this performance. But while the underlying competencies are not focused on, they do play a role in the explications. Skinner noted throughout his career that phylogenetic factors are important in shaping the organism:

“Just as we point to the contingencies of survival to explain an unconditioned reflex, so we point out to contingencies of reinforcement to explain a conditioned reflex.” (Skinner 1974 p. 43)

He emphasised that natural selection shaped the structure of the organism through the scythe of survival of the fittest, in analogous manner to the way operant conditioning shaped the behaviour of the organism through selection by consequence. In Skinner’s view selection by consequences rules in both phylogeny and ontogeny. And as early as the mid 60’s behaviourists the Breland’s were emphasising instinctive drift would ensure that different organisms would not be susceptible to have their behaviour shaped in the same way because of their different instinctive natures.

            Analogously, Relational Frame Theorists don’t deny that any prediction and control we gain needs to be explained by underlying genetic, epigenetic, and neural structures. It is just that their primary emphasis is on emergent behavioural data which can be predicted and controlled through behavioural principles. Thus, while relational frames, are emergent phenomena discovered through behavioural training and testing, Hayes does try to explain their emergence as resulting from a combination of genetic constraints and social learning. Thus, he appeals to group selection favouring a cooperative instinct which makes the acquisition of relational frames such as coordination more likely and speculates on how other frames can be derived from a combination of coordination and equivalence (Hayes and Sanford 2014). Nonetheless, the primary emphasis in both relational frame theory and Skinnenarian behaviourism is on prediction and control of the organism using behavioural principles.  

            As discussed above Chomsky wasn’t against performance data per-se, on the contrary he believed that the only theory of performance of any theoretical interest was a theory which took on board competence-based insights (Chomsky 1965 p. 16). Chomsky’s claim has a degree of truth to it; but it is obviously not the whole story. As discussed above in the 60 years since Chomsky wrote Aspects behaviourists have discovered performance data which has ample theoretical interest. The performance data elicited by the behavioural tests, such as stimulus equivalence, rule following contingency insensitivity, relational frames are of great theoretical interest. But to yield a theoretically interesting theory of this performance data we will need to do so in terms of underlying competence systems.

            Behaviourists sometimes do try to explain behaviour in terms of underlying competencies. As we saw above Skinner’s notion of phylogenetic shaping can be used to explain the Breland’s notion of instinctive drift, which is used in a theoretical explanation of animal’s divergent behaviour under schedules of reinforcement. Likewise, Quine appealed to a phylogenetically shaped similarity space which underlay our capacity to successfully engage in induction. However, when it comes to emergent phenomena such as stimulus equivalence and relational frames there has been a reluctance by some theorists to explain the phenomenon in terms of underlying innate mechanisms. In the next section I will give an example from psychological behaviourism which aims to explain relation framing in terms of evolved underlying competencies, and I will then discuss an example of a philosophical behaviourist explaining his data in terms of underlying competencies. This will be proof in principle that some behaviourists do make a distinction between competence and performance and do use idealizations in their theoretical endeavours.

   Quine and Relational Frame Theory.

            In this section I will outline and discuss an attempt by Hayes and Sanford (2014) to explain our species-specific capacity to engage in relational framing in terms of group selection for a cooperative instinct. This section will demonstrate that behaviourists do appeal to competencies to explain behavioural patterns to explain novel behaviour when necessary and that furthermore they routinely engage in idealizations to explain data. I will then further develop this point by showing how it isn’t just psychological behaviourists who appeal to underlying competencies and idealizations to explain behaviour. Some philosophical behaviourists do so as well. This will be demonstrated by evaluating Quines work in this area.

In Hayes and Sanford (2014) they discuss evolution of our ability to engage in verbal behaviour. To understand this capacity, they explain it in terms of abilities humans partially share with non-verbal creatures such as (1) the ability to use vocalizations to regulate the behaviour of others (shared with many mammals), (2) Social Referencing (dogs and Chimpanzees can do this), (3) Joint attention and non-verbal forms of perspective taking (chimps and apes) (4) Non-arbitrary Relational learning (all animals). And they argue that these competencies were modified through group selection. They note that a cooperative instinct within a group will give them the ability to out compete other groups.

With a Cooperative Instinct in place, if two humans are near an apple tree and both know how to say apple when they see an apple. If the apple is out of reach for person A and person A says “apple” then if it is within reach for person B then they will get it for person A. (Ibid p. 121). They argue that it would take the capacity of perspective taking along with the capacity for cooperation to bridge the gap between this epistemological triangle. They call this the beginning of a person’s capacity to engage in a frame of coordination. People acquire the ability to know that “apple” → apple and apple →”apple”. Thus, they know that the sound refers to the object and the object is referred to by the sound. This relationship can then come under contextual control of the “is” relation: Apple is “Apple” and “Apple” is Apple.

Deriving this relation of identity between the sound and the word will be helped through reinforcement for providing the object when the word is said, and having the object provided when you say the word. Relational Frame Theorists have argued that this ability to derive this frame (which is species specific), is made possible through coopting our capacities such as joint attention, the ability to modify others behaviours through vocalizations, social referencing, and non-arbitrary relation framing with our cooperative instinct.

Once this frame of coordination was acquired humans would then have the capacity to recognize mutuality in a frame. And they argue that repeated application of mutuality would give an organism the ability to use combinatorial entailment (ibid p.123). Thus, on this conception the capacity to relationally frame is created primarily by our cooperative instinct. So in effect they explain our capacity to relational frame in terms of underlying competencies such as social referencing, joint attention, the ability to control others using vocal signals, non-arbitrary relational responding being modified in terms of a human specific cooperative instinct shaped by natural selection. In this instance the novel performance data is explained in terms of underlying competencies. They aren’t just describing behavioural patterns they are explaining their arrival in terms of underlying competencies.

                     Quine Idealization

As discussed above the competence-performance distinction is aligned with the notion of idealizations where you can abstract out from aspects of a phenomenon and deal with more tractable subject matters. Thus, the scientist can be dealing with frictionless plans, or humans not subject to memory limitations or distractions etc. The charge made by Jackendoff, and others was that behaviourists don’t use idealizations and hence they have no resources to make the competence-performance distinction. We have seen that this is simply not true when it comes to behavioural science which from the start is up to its eyes in idealizing assumptions. This is true of not just of behaviourists in the scientific sphere but also of prominent behaviourists working on philosophical problems.

Quine’s conception of language is famously terse. While he talks of a child acquiring and being shaped by a language of his peers. He typically focuses on things such as observation sentences. There is little in his conception of language about other uses of language such as interrogatives. Quine justifies this because he is interested in language only in so far as it pertains to epistemology and ontology. Hence, he engages in an simplifying idealization when dealing with science.  Thus in ‘The Roots of Reference’ Quine speaks of the fact that requesting makes up a large part of our linguistic usage, but he doesn’t account for it because it has little relevance in his attempts to explain how we acquire our scientific theory of the world (Quine 1973 p. 46). And later in the same book he notes that he doesn’t want a factual account of how children acquire English, rather he is concerned with telling a plausible story of how we go from infancy to developing a regimented language of science (ibid p. 92). Quine made the same point again in his Mind and Verbal Dispositions:

“One and the same little sentence may be uttered for various purposes: to warn, remind, to obtain possession, to gain confirmation, to gain admiration, or to give pleasure by pointing something out… somehow we must further divide; we must find some significant central strand to extract from the tangle…Truth will do nicely…a man understands a sentence in so far as he knows its truth conditions…this kind of understanding stops short of humour, irony, innuendo, and other literary values, but it goes a long way. In particular it is all we can ask of an understanding of science. (Quine 2008 pp. 448-249).

Again, we can see that Quine is abstracting away from various uses of language because they aren’t useful to him in sketching his story of how we go from stimulus to science. Quine, like his behavioural science colleagues, is engaging in idealizations at every step of his philosophical project. Furthermore, Quine is appealing to underlying competencies to explain how it is that humans go from stimulus to science (Quine 1980 p. 6, Quine 1989 p. 348, Quine 1998 p. 4). He appeals to innate similarity quality space to explain our ability to be able to differentially reinforced, an innate perceptual similarity space to explain our convergence on stimulus meaning, as well as appealing to body mindedness to explain children’s ability to understand object-permanence.

                             Conclusion

In this paper I have demonstrated that behaviourists of both philosophical and scientific bent do indeed make use of both idealizations and of a distinction between competence and performance in their work. Despite the criticisms of Chomsky and his followers; behaviourism’s focus on performance doesn’t necessitate them ignoring competence or shunning the use of idealizations. It is probable that the followers of Chomsky will be un-moved they will note that there has been no behavioural work which can account for the grammatical regularities which are discovered in linguistics. And this I would agree with. Behaviourism even modern behaviourism still hasn’t demonstrated that it has the conceptual resources to handle the syntax of natural language. Nonetheless, we are increasingly discovering more and more interesting performance regularities through behavioural research. These data do need to be explained in terms of underlying competencies. But the discovery of these interesting facts about our behaviour (including Verbal Behaviour), indicate that pace Chomsky we can discover interesting facts about performance prior to having a worked-out theory of competence. In fact, behavioural research has lead us towards achieving a greater understanding of the competencies underlying them not vice-versa. With the sciences of biolinguistics and behavioural science still in their infancies there is still a lot of data to acquire and experimental work to be done. But any attempts to understand either side will involve a greater attention to the what the practitioner of each discipline is doing and not relying on caricatures.

                                          References

Barnes-Holmes, D. 2000. Behavioural Pragmatism: No Place for Reality and Truth”, The Behaviour Analyst 23 pp. 191-202.

Barnes-Holmes, D. 2005. “Behavioural Pragmatism is A-Ontological, Not Anti-Realist: A Reply to Tonneau”, Behaviour and Philosophy 33 pp. 67-79.

Baum, W. 2002. “From Molecular to Molar: A Paradigm Shift in Behaviour Analysis”. Journal of the Experimental Analysis of Behaviour. 78 (1) pp. 95-116.

Chomsky, N. 1965. Aspects of a Theory of Syntax. MA: MIT Press.

Christensen, M, H, & Chater, N. “The Now-or-Never Bottleneck: A fundamental Constraint on language”. Behavioural and Brain sciences 39 (2016).

Christensen, M, H, & Chater, N.  2023. The Language Game. Random House. Penguin.

Collins, J. 2007. “Linguistic Competence Without Knowledge of Language”. Philosophy Compass 2 (6) pp. 880-895)

Dymond, S, & Roche, B, (2013) Advances in Relational Frame Theory. Context Press. New Harbinger Publications.

Galizio, M. (1979). “Contingency-shaped and rule-governed behaviour: Instructional control of human loss avoidance.” Journal of the Experimental Analysis of Behaviour. 31, pp. 53-70.

Ginsburg, S., & Jablonka, E,. 2019. The Evolution of the Sensitive Soul.  MIT Press. Cambridge MA.

Hayes, L, J, & Thompson, S. 1989. “Stimulus Equivalence and Rule-Following”. Journal of the Experimental Analysis of Behaviour. 52 (3) pp. 275-291.

Hayes, S, & Barnes-Holmes, D, & Roche, B. 2001. Relational Frame Theory: A post Skinnearian Account of Language and Cognition. Springer Science & Business Media.

Hayes, S. 2014. “Cooperation Came First: Evolution and Human Cognition.” Journal of the Experimental Analys of Behaviour 101 pp. 112-129.

Hofstadter, D, R, Moser avid J, M., “To Err is human; To study error-making is cognitive science”. Michigan Quarterly Review, 28 (2), pp. 185-215.

Jackendoff, R. 2002. Foundations of Language. Great Clarendon Street. Oxford University Press.

Kemp, G. 2017. “Quine, Publicity and Pre-Established Harmony”, Protosociology 34 pp. 59-72.

Lakoff, G. 1987. Women, Fire, and Dangerous Things.  The University of Chicago Press.

Palmer, D. 2023. “Towards a Behavioural Interpretation of English Grammar.” Perspectives on Behaviour Science. 46 (3) pp. 521-538.

Pepper, S, C. 1942. World Hypotheses: A Study in Evidence. University of California Press.

Quine, W. 1953.  From a Logical Point of View. Harvard University Press. Cambridge MA.

Quine, W. 1974. The Roots of Reference. La Salle. Open Court Press.

Quine, W. 1995. From Stimulus to Science. Cambridge. Mass. Harvard University Press.

Quine, W. 1996. “Progress on Two Fronts”, The Journal of Philosophy. 93/4 pp. 159-163

Quine, W. 2008. “The Flowering of Thought in Language” pp. 478-484 in Follesdal & Quine (EDS) Quine: Confessions of a Confirmed Extensionalist.

Rescorla, R. 1969. “Pavlovian Conditioned Inhibition.” Psychological Bulletin 72 (2) pp. 77

Sautter, R, & Leblanc L, “Empirical Applications of Skinner’s Analysis of Verbal Behaviour with Humans”. The Analysis of Verbal Behaviour 22 pp. 35-48.

Shimoff, E, Catania, A, Matthews, B, 1981. “Unstructured Human Responding: Sensitivity of Low Rate Performances to Schedule Contingencies.” Journal of Experimental Analysis of Behaviour. 36 (2) pp.207-220.

Sidman, M. 1971. “Reading and Auditory Visual Equivalences”. Journal of Speech and Hearing Research. 14 (1) pp. 5-13.

Skinner, B.F. 1957. Verbal Behaviour. New Jersey: Prentice-Hall Inc.

Skinner, B.F. 1974. About Behaviourism. Knoph Doubleday Publishing Group.

Skinner, B.F. 1984. “Contingencies and Rules”. Behavioural and Brain Sciences. 7 (4) pp. 607-613.

Smith, L. D. 1986. Behaviourism and Logical Positivism: A Reassessment of The Alliance. California: Stanford University Press.

Wijnen, F, “Incidental word and sound errors in young speakers”, Journal of Memory and Language 31 pp.734-755.

Wilson, D, S, & Hayes, S. 2018 Evolution and Contextual Behavioural Science. Context Press. New Harbinger Publications Inc.


 

[2]  There is a debate within behavioural science on whether scientists are studying of classes or individuals see Baum ‘From Molecular to Molar: A Paradigm Shift in Behaviour Analysis’ (2002).

 A short blog-post re-written by ChatGpt in the style of Richard Dawkins

The Setting

The act of referring to objects, so effortlessly performed in everyday discourse, belies the complex web of philosophical inquiry it has spurred since the dawn of analytic philosophy. In the annals of this intellectual tradition, a recurring motif emerges: the relentless quest to mend the perceived fractures in the relationship between words and the world they represent. As the century unfolded, a dichotomy crystallized within the realm of linguistic philosophy. On one side stood the cognitivists, disciples of Chomsky, who espoused the view of language as an internal computational apparatus for thought. According to Chomsky’s doctrine, language itself did not possess inherent reference but served as a conduit for expressing thoughts about the external realm. On the opposing front were the behaviourists, led by Skinner, who conceptualized language as verbal behavior moulded by environmental contingencies. Skinner’s contention that the traditional notion of reference was dispensable gave rise to the notion of the “tact,” a verbal operant subject to control by non-verbal stimuli and shaped by the three-term contingency.

Despite their discordant philosophies, both camps found common ground in their dismissal of the reference relation as dissected by analytic philosophers. This scepticism toward linguistic philosophy’s pursuits of clarity and repair continues. But work over the last half a century has laid the groundwork for some convergence between analytic philosophy and behavioural science. In this exploration, we delve into the fertile terrain where analytic philosophy and behavioural science intersect, focusing on the burgeoning field of Relational Frame Theory (RFT). Through an examination of the perspectives of Quine and relational frame theorists, we embark on a journey to unravel the intricacies of observation sentences—how they are acquired, developed, and intertwined with our perception of the world. Join us as we navigate the intricate labyrinth of language and cognition, seeking to illuminate the elusive nature of referentiality and its implications for our understanding of the human mind.

              The Evolution of language

In their groundbreaking work, Hayes and Sanford (2014) delve into the evolutionary origins of our verbal behavior, painting a vivid picture of how our linguistic abilities evolved over time. They dissect our communication skills, drawing parallels between humans and other non-verbal creatures, highlighting shared traits such as vocalizations to influence behavior and social referencing. Arguing from the vantage point of group selection, Hayes and Sanford suggest that our cooperative instincts played a pivotal role in shaping our linguistic capacities. They illustrate this through a compelling scenario: two individuals near an apple tree, both equipped with the word “apple.” When one person vocalizes the word and the fruit is out of reach, the other steps in to retrieve it, fostering cooperation and mutual understanding. This cooperative dynamic, they contend, marks the genesis of our ability to engage in a frame of coordination, where words seamlessly align with their referents. Through reinforcement and shared experiences, individuals develop a nuanced understanding of the relationship between sounds and objects, paving the way for combinatorial entailment and the intricate web of relational frames. In essence, Hayes and Sanford propose that our cooperative instincts underpin our capacity to frame and derive meaning from language, ushering in a new era of understanding in the evolutionary origins of human communication.

Once this frame of coordination was acquired humans would then have the capacity to recognize mutuality in a frame. And they argue that repeated application of mutuality would give an organism the ability to use combinatorial entailment (ibid p.123). Thus, on this conception the capacity to relationally frame is created primarily by our cooperative instinct.

   Individual or Shared Behavioural Streams

In the intricate narrative spun by Sanford and Hayes (2014), the spotlight falls on the profound interplay between human cognition and cooperative instincts, casting a revealing light on the evolution of verbal behavior. Central to their thesis is the notion of coordination between words and objects, a feat achieved through social derivation and contextual control over the “is” relation. Illustrating their argument with the allegory of two individuals wielding the word “apple” as a Mand, Sanford and Hayes beckon us into a world where language becomes a conduit for shared experiences and mutual understanding. Yet, lurking beneath the surface lies a critique of individualistic interpretations, epitomized by Barnes-Holmes (2000), who dissected such instances of triangulation within the confines of individual behavioural streams. In this intricate dance of cognition and cooperation, the tale takes a twist as the narrative shifts to the realm of joint attention. Here, the shared object of experience emerges as the linchpin, transcending individual streams and fostering a communal understanding. While behavioural pragmatists grapple with the ontological underpinnings, their reluctance to delve into intersubjective agreement leaves a void in their narrative, one that can only be filled by acknowledging the symbiotic relationship between individual streams and communal experiences. Thus, as the story unfolds, Sanford and Hayes beckon us to embark on a journey through the labyrinth of human cognition, where language and cooperation intertwine to shape our collective understanding of the world.

         Cometh the Hour Cometh the Man

Enter Quine, the philosophical voyager navigating the treacherous waters of linguistic ambiguity and cognitive convergence. Armed with intellect and inquiry, Quine set out to unravel the enigma of shared understanding amidst the cacophony of sensory receptors. In Quine’s labyrinth of inquiry, the conundrum of observation sentences loomed large, casting shadows of doubt upon the very fabric of linguistic communion. While his behavioural contemporaries grappled with the intricacies of Mand and Tact, Quine delved into the depths of epistemological and semantic inquiry, seeking to unveil the secrets of meaning and consensus. Yet, amidst the philosophical fog, parallels emerged between Quine’s quest and the behavioural pragmatists’ plight. Both faced the daunting task of reconciling individual streams of experience with the communal tapestry of cognition, each seeking solace in the embrace of naturalistic explanation. Quine’s solution, an appeal to perceptual harmony and empathetic resonance, stood as a beacon of enlightenment amidst the turbulent seas of inquiry. Through the lens of empathy, Quine discerned the threads of joint attention and social referencing, weaving a tapestry of understanding that transcended individual perspectives. And yet, the tension persisted between Quine’s ontological aspirations and the pragmatists’ yearning for epistemological clarity. As Barnes-Holmes et al. posited the notion of separate behavioural streams, Quine’s empathy-driven paradigm stood as a testament to the interconnectedness of human cognition. In the end, Quine’s journey served as a testament to the intricate dance of intellect and instinct, weaving a narrative of inquiry and insight that continues to resonate across the landscape of philosophical discourse.

Barnes-Holmes, Subjective Idealism and Behaviourism

                           Introduction

David Barnes-Holmes (2000) in his ‘Behavioural Pragmatism: No Place for Reality and Truth’ criticized Quine for offering a non-solution to the problem of homology. The problem of homology sprung up when Quine was trying to explain how different subjects could assent or dissent from observation sentences. Quine tried to cash out the stimulus meaning of observation sentences in terms of the triggering of sensory receptors. But this led to a difficulty of explaining how two people whose sensory receptors could be triggered differently could converge on stimulus meanings. Quine’s non-solution was that the scientist in practice could ignore the problem because it wouldn’t affect their experiments (Quine 1974 p. 24). Barnes-Holmes argued that while Quine was counselling to ignore the problem based on pragmatic principles contextual behaviourists could remove the problem altogether by adopting a consistent pragmatist approach (Barnes-Holmes 2000 p. 197).

                Quine’s Darwinian Solution

            But Barnes-Holmes didn’t note that Quine (1996) had already come up with a different solution to the problem of homology which didn’t involve merely ignoring it on pragmatic grounds (Barnes-Holmes 2000 p. 196). Quine’s original definition of stimulus-meaning as being provided by the triggering of sensory receptors was difficult to sustain because of his publicity criterion in relation to observation sentences (Kemp 2019 p. 60). Given that people’s sensory receptors could be triggered in a myriad of different ways there is no real justification for assuming shared sensory triggering’s are responsible for our agreement on whether to assent or to dissent from an observation sentence at all.

            Quine though thought that shared stimulus meanings could be accounted for by assuming that humans have a shared perceptual similarity space which underlay their grouping of things together (Quine 1996 p. 161). This similarity space would be partly innate though modifiable through training (Quine 1995 p. 21). He argued that this perceptual similarity space would have survival value and hence would be passed on through natural selection. Put in Skinnerian terminology Quine speculated that the phylogenetic contingencies of survival would be responsible for our perceptual similarity space. And he argued that the nature of these similarity spaces could be determined empirically:

“But perception for all its mentalistic overtones, is accessible to behavioural criteria. It shows itself in conditioning responses. Thus, suppose we provide an animal with a screen to look at and a lever to press. He finds that the pressed lever brings a pellet of food when the screen shows a circular stripe, and that it brings a shock when the screen shows four spots spaced in a semi-circular arc. Now we present him with these same four spots, arranged as before, but supplemented with three more to suggest the complementary semicircle. If the animal pressed the lever, he may be said to have perceived the circular Gestalt rather than the component spots. (Quine 1974 p. 4)

All this is well within the remit of typical animal studies.

Quine was bringing in the notion of a partially innate perceptual similarity shared amongst humans to explain how we converge on the same stimulus meanings for observation sentences. And observation sentences were obviously meant as our empirical check point for our theory of the world. The purpose of this was to give us a naturalistic theory of how we go from Stimulus to Science. And shared innate perceptual similarities cashed out in terms of natural selection and neural structures is sufficiently objective for Quine to rest satisfied with the explanation.

    Barnes-Holmes Behavioural Pragmatism

Barnes-Holmes never mentioned Quine’s Darwinian attempt of a solution to the problem of homology. So obviously he never framed any reply. Before, considering what he may think of Quine’s attempted solution I will first briefly outline his own behavioural pragmatist solution to the homology problem and then relate his attempted solution to Quine’s Darwinian Solution.

 When outlining his behavioural pragmatism Barnes-Holmes notes that it relies on three key assumptions to justify the position. Assumption 1: What is known is always a behavioural function. Assumption 2: The activity of each organism participates in a different behavioural stream. Assumption 3: The activity of the behavioural pragmatist participates in a behavioural stream (Ibid p. 198).

            Each of these assumptions are extremely controversial. Assumption 1 argues that what is known is always a behavioural function not a behaviour independent reality. It isn’t particularly controversial to state that we know things through a function of our behaviour. Barnes-Holmes gives the example of an apple and states that we know the apple through its functions such-as how it elicits stimulations like salivation, or it being a discriminative stimulus for Verbal Behaviour such as ‘this is an apple’, or as reinforcing stimulus for saying something like ‘give me an apple’ (Ibid p. 197). The few examples he gives involve the ontogenetic interaction of a human subject with an apple. He doesn’t mention any phylogenetic factors which would go into the human’s behavioural interaction with the apple. Though presumably he would admit that phylogenetic factors may play such a role. Skinner long stressed that some phylogenetic factors will play a role in an organism’s behaviour (Skinner 1974 p. 228). Likewise, Hayes and Sanford (2014) suggest that to ensure that asking for an apple will have reinforcing consequences we will have to assume a cooperative instinct.

            None of this will be particularly controversial. There are empirical details to fill in about the nature of our behavioural interactions with entities such as apples. And debates about the role of perception as opposed to brute behaviour in our knowledge of things like apples. But depending on how we construe behaviour it is eminently sensible to suggest that we only know something though our behavioural functions with it. But Barnes-Holmes goes further than this. He isn’t content to claim we only know something through behavioural interactions with it; he goes on contrast this with a belief in a physical apple at all:

“In commonsense terms, the apple is a physical thing that exists independently of behavior. For the behavioural pragmatist, however, the apple is defined only in terms of its behavioural functions that emerge in a particular stream of behavioural interactions.” (Ibid p. 197)

In the above quote the notion of a physical thing which exists independent of behaviour is rejected. He isn’t claiming that a mind independent apple doesn’t exist; rather he merely states that the behavioural pragmatist’s definition of apple doesn’t rely on notions of physical objects that exist independent of behaviours. Though he does go on to say that behavioural pragmatist will sometimes talk as if some objects exist independent of behaviour (Ibid p. 198). But such talk involves no ontological commitment as Verbal Behaviour in the technical sense doesn’t ‘refer’ or ‘correspond’ to an external reality (Ibid p. 199).

            It is important to be clear about the commitments they are making. When Barnes-Holmes is making claims about defining objects in terms of their behavioural functions the examples he gives of behaviour are of classical conditioning where an object elicits salivation in an organism, discriminative stimulus which increases the probability of a particular tact being used, and operant processes being involved in making the likelihood of a Mand being used increase (Ibid p. 197). A difficulty with this conception is that internal to theorising about the origins of Verbal Behaviour there is a consensus that Verbal Behaviour first emerged about 100,000 years ago (Hayes and Sandford 2014 p. 114). Furthermore, there is compelling evidence that the capacity for a creature to learn through conditioning of any kind began about 520 million years ago (Ginsburg, S, & Jablonka, E. 2019 p. 293). So, if we think of things such as Cyanobacteria which our best theories tell us existed for billions of years before either the evolution of a capacity to be conditioned or a capacity to engage in Verbal Behaviour (Schirrmeister et al 2015 p. 777). Given the capacities Barnes-Holmes uses to illustrate behavioural functions we use to define an object, he appears to be committed to the view that Cyanobacteria did not exist until creatures with a sophisticated behavioural capacity emerged on the scene, with the capacity to engage with them is a manner sophisticated enough to develop a verbal and non-verbal repertoire in relation to them. It could be argued that this position is a behavioural version of Berkeleyan Subjective Idealism where we must deny the existence of a behavioural independent world.

            Barnes-Holmes would deny that he is engaging in any type of Idealism. He has argued he is not making some anti-realist argument, rather he is making an a-ontological claim about reality. He says that the anti-realist is arguing that either nothing exists beyond scientific language, or that scientific language doesn’t capture reality as it really is (Barnes-Holmes 2005 p. 68). Whereas he defines a-ontological claims as claims which remain silent on behaviour independent reality (Ibid p. 68). Furthermore, he would argue that Cyanobacteria do enter into the behavioural stream of our working scientists, so we are therefore justified in postulating their existence internal to our overall theory of the world. But given that our best theories tell us that entities existed prior to creatures who have behavioural capacities like the ones Barnes-Holmes mentions; why remain silent about their ontological status. Why remain happy to say that it is sometimes ok to talk as if these entities existed, or that to the extent that these entities enter a scientist’s behavioural stream we are justified in saying they exist?

            Why not accord these entities robust realist ontological status? The following passage is instructive as an explanation of Barnes-Holmes reluctance:

“Assumption 3, however, appears to preclude the possibility, in behavioural pragmatism, of finding a scientific truth statement that corresponds to an ontological reality. In effect, if the scientific activity of the behavioural pragmatist is the product of a behavioural history, then he or she can never claim to have found an ontological truth, because a different or more extended history may have produced a different truth (an ontological truth, by definition, is immutable, absolute, and final).” (Barnes-Holmes 2000 p. 198).

So, assumption 3 notes that even the behaviourist’s behaviour is a product of their learning history as they interact with their own behavioural stream. Which means that a different learning history would give them a different theory.  From this Barnes-Holmes concludes that since an ontological truth is by definition “immutable, absolute, and final”, contingent creatures such as us can never arrive at such ontological truths.

            But one wonders why he thinks that we need to parse ontological truths as truths which are immutable absolute and final. Ontology is the philosophical discipline which aims to discover the basic furniture of the universe. To discover what is in the most general sense possible. In traditional philosophy ontology was opposed to epistemology. Famously, Kant argued that reality as it is in itself is unknowable, and that we can only know reality in so far as it conforms to our mode of cognition. So true reality in its ontological form is something which we can never know. Hence, Kant argued that metaphysics should give up the proud name of ontology. In this sense of ontology, we cannot say anything about ontology; even statements about whether it is “immutable, absolute, and final” would be out of place because whatever the nature of ontology beyond our mode of cognition we would not be justified in speaking about it.  So, it is doubtful, whether Barnes-Holmes meant ontology in the sense the Kantian sense.

            Older versions of ontology which would have begun with Plato would involve studying entities in the world and trying to discover their accidental and essential natures. The discovery of essences would in this sense would typically be conceived of as “immutable, absolute and final”. Metaphysics in this sense would have ontological purport and is still studied to this day in philosophy departments. If Barnes-Holmes is critical of this type of ontology that is one thing, however, it doesn’t follow that because the behavioural scientist is critical of ontology in Plato’s sense that it should therefore become a-ontological.

            There is another strand of ontology which doesn’t involve appeals to ‘immutable, absolute and final” properties and that version of ontology was developed by Quine who Barnes-Holmes discussed in the paper. It is surprising therefore that he didn’t criticise Quine’s view of ontology directly.

            Barnes-Holmes argues that the issue of scientific truth is defined ultimately in terms of whether it achieves certain goals; and for the behaviourist the ultimate goal is prediction and control. So, ontology doesn’t come into the issue at all. He explicates his a-ontological position by arguing that “no fundamental or final or absolute assumptions are ever made about the nature or substance of behaviour independent reality” (Barnes Holmes 2005 p. 68). In effect they ignore issues in relation to realism-vs-anti-realism and stick doing behavioural science involving the prediction and control of organism’s understudy.

“Functional relations, at least in behavior analysis, are correlational, and no mentalistic, cognitive, or intentional act of reference from the response to an ontologically real stimulus is implied when functional-analytic terms are used in a behavioural explanation. For the behavioural pragmatist, therefore, a technical analysis of ontological talk will be cast in terms of patterns of stimulus-response-stimulus interactions, not semantic reference, literal meaning, or some form of word-referent correspondence. The procedural instruction “set the tone to between x and y cycles per second,” for example, could be interpreted as a relational network of derived stimulus relations (Barnes-Holmes, Hayes, & Dymond, 2001; Barnes-Holmes, O’Hora, et. al., 2001) or an instructional stimulus composed of Tacts, intraverbals, relational autoclitics, and the like (Skinner, 1957), or perhaps a combination of both interpretations (Barnes-Holmes, et. al., 2000). In neither case, however, is semantic reference or literal correspondence to an ontological reality included as part of the explanatory nomenclature. The technical terms of behavior analysis are simply empty with respect to ontological reality, and thus neither realism nor antirealism is implied.” (Barnes-Holmes 2005 pp. 73-74)

Despite above writing that the technical terms of behavioural analysis are ontologically empty, he notes that ontological talk is regularly used in report sections of daily articles and in ordinary scientific activities (ibid p. 74), arguing that such talk is fine as long as it doesn’t involve talking about the fundamental nature of reality.

            The idea that it is ok for behavioural analysts to talk about a behaviour independent reality when describing the results of their experiments, but this talk isn’t to be taken seriously as a description of the reality.  Part of the motivation is that Barnes-Holmes wants to avoid being committed to making assumptions about the fundamental or absolute nature of reality. So committed  is he to avoiding speaking about absolute reality is he that he goes as far to define something as true in so far as it achieves certain scientific goals (prediction and control). Aside from the fact that this assumption is arbitrary; why for example is prediction and control given priority over explanatory depth?

            More importantly the behaviourist can achieve their goals without bending over backwards and trying to eschew all talk about a mind independent reality. A more realistic goal would be to treat ontology as a part of science; and treat ontological commitment as the working out of what theoretical presuppositions cannot be done away with to make sense of our total theory of the world. If we cannot make sense of our experimental results without presupposing certain entities, then we are justified in admitting into our ontology. Quine, argued that a good technique to lay bare the ontological commitments of a science are to translate into the syntax of first order logic arguing that:

“a theory is committed to those and only those entities to which bound variables of the theory must be capable of referring in order that the affirmations made in the theory be true” (Quine, 1953 pp. 13-14)

And he used this technique to try and dis-entangle philosophical disputes on ontological commitment in subjects like mathematics.

            It could be argued that while mathematicians and physicists can do their work without solving debates about ontological commitment all behavioural analysts are asking for is the freedom to do their work without solving debates about ontological commitment. However, I don’t think that this is a fair way of interpreting the debate. The behaviourists aren’t just eschewing ontological talk in some innocent theory independent way; rather they are making truth relative to their own personal goals; and judging a theory as to whether meets those goals adequately. Anything outside of these personal goals are deemed irrelevant.

     Quine and the Pre-Established Harmony.

Barnes-Holmes describes the problem of homology as a problem which arises when we assume a correspondence between observation sentences and ontological reality (Barnes-Holmes 2000 p. 195). Quine’s attempted solution does indeed make assumptions about ontological reality. His assumptions are largely physicalist. He is assuming mind independent world with features such that an organism must track if it is to survive, he assuming that creatures whose neural structures with innate standards of perceptual similarity which tend to harmonize with trends in the environment will be more likely to survive than animals whose innate structures don’t harmonize with the environment (Quine 2008 p.204).  And this assumption is then used to explain how human’s shared neural perceptual similarity structures will explain how they converge on stimulus meanings of observation sentences.

            One may or may not agree with Quine’s account of how humans shared perceptual similarity standards lead to similar stimulus meanings which accounts for agreement on observation sentences. But his account is no more ontologically profligate than behavioural scientists appeal to group selection for cooperation to explain the emergence of frames of coordination in children’s ontogeny (Hayes 2014 p. 123). Or when behaviourists explain taste aversion in rats through natural selection resulting in the temporal parameters of classical conditioning becoming distorted (Wilson and Hayes 2018 p. 53).

            It could be replied that behaviourists like Barnes-Holmes have difficulties not with appeals to neural structures, or sensory receptors being impinged on. Rather they want such explanations cashed out functionally instead of in terms of shared structures (Barnes-Holmes 2000 p. 201). But this reading cannot be correct. Behaviourists emphasize the central importance prediction in their theories. And Quine’s appeal to shared structures is making predictions which are eminently testable by future science. It would be churlish to critique Quine for appealing to shared structures if this appeal involves empirical check points and predictions which could be tested. Furthermore, explanations of distortions in classical conditioning in taste aversion which behaviourists unproblematically study involve appeals to shared structure in rats.

            Barnes-Holmes though could argue that it is not just Quine’s appeals to shared structure which he has difficulties with. He also had difficulties with Quine’s appeals to Observation Sentences as part of his check points which are used to ensure that theories are tested for truth. Barnes-Holmes has difficulties with any non-pragmatic appeal to truth as his assumption 3 that scientists views develop as a result of their learning history means that with a different learning history, they may have held different theories of the world. Barnes-Holmes believes that assumption 3 means that we can never hold “immutable, final, absolute” ontological truths. But when Quine speaks about ontology, he is not speaking in terms of “absolute, immutable, and final” truths. Quine’s entire philosophy is built around the concept of radical revisability of our overall theories of the world, and no aspect of our web-of-belief is immune from potential revision; including mathematics or logic.  Therefore Barnes-Holmes criticisms completely miss the mark when it comes to Quine, as when he speaks about ontology he is never speaking about absolute, immutable and final truths.  

                         Bibliography

Barnes-Holmes, D. 2000. Behavioural Pragmatism: No Place for Reality and Truth”, The Behaviour Analyst 23 pp. 191-202.

Barnes-Holmes, D. 2005. “Behavioural Pragmatism is A-Ontological, Not Anti-Realist: A Reply to Tonneau”, Behaviour and Philosophy 33 pp. 67-79.

Ginsburg, S., & Jablonka, E,. 2019. The Evolution of the Sensitive Soul.  MIT Press. Cambridge MA.

Hayes, S. 2014. “Cooperation Came First: Evolution and Human Cognition.” Journal of the Experimental Analys of Behaviour 101 pp. 112-129.

Kemp, G. 2017. “Quine, Publicity and Pre-Established Harmony”, Protosociology 34 pp. 59-72.  

Quine, W. 1953.  From a Logical Point of View. Harvard University Press. Cambridge MA.

Quine, W. 1974. The Roots of Reference. La Salle. Open Court Press.

Quine, W. 1995. From Stimulus to Science. Cambridge. Mass. Harvard University Press.

Quine, W. 1996. “Progress on Two Fronts”, The Journal of Philosophy. 93/4 pp. 159-163

Quine, W. 2008. “The Flowering of Thought in Language” pp. 478-484 in Follesdal & Quine (EDS) Quine: Confessions of a Confirmed Extensionalist.

Wilson, D, S, & Hayes, S. 2018 Evolution and Contextual Behavioural Science. Context Press. New Harbinger Publications Inc.

Schirrmeister BE, Gugger M, Donoghue PCJ. 2015. “Cyanobacteria and the Great Oxidation Event: evidence from genes and fossils”. Palaeontology 58: 769–785.

Skinner, B.F. 1974. About Behaviourism. Vintage Books. New York.

Chomsky ‘Psychology and Ideology’ 50 Years On.

Introduction

            In this blog post I will discuss Noam Chomsky’s 1971 paper ‘Psychology and Ideology’ where Chomsky critiques Skinner’s popular science book ‘Beyond Freedom and Dignity’. In Beyond Freedom and Dignity Skinner claimed that freewill was an illusion and we could explain it away using an effective behavioural science. And once we did this we would be in a position to use behavioural science to engineer a more effective society than the one we currently live in.

I will argue that while Chomsky sometimes caricatures Skinner, and he is blind to the strengths of behaviourism as a discipline, his criticisms still hit the mark. Skinner’s remarks in ‘Beyond Freedom and Dignity’, exaggerated what the science of behaviour was capable of in 1971, and is still beyond what behavioural science can achieve 50 years later. To this end, Chomsky’s 1971 paper did the field of psychology and philosophy a favour with its terse criticism of Skinner’s attempt at popular science.

Psychology and Ideology

 At the beginning of ‘Psychology and Ideology’ Chomsky noted when reflecting on psychological claims that we need to ask two different kinds of questions: (1) What is the scientific status of the claims, (2) What social or ideological needs do they serve. He correctly noted that these two claims are logically independent. He argues that Skinner’s empirical claims are vacuous and completely without scientific merit. And he argues that because of their null scientific status they can serve the purposes of any would be dictator as rhetoric whether the dictator was on the left or the right.

            Chomsky even goes as far to argue that the these of ‘Beyond Freedom and Dignity’ results in the whole project being incoherent:

 “But if his thesis is true, then there is also no point in his having written the book or our reading it. For the only point could be to modify behavior, and behavior, according to the thesis, is entirely controlled by arrangement of reinforcers. Therefore, reading the book can modify behavior only if it is a reinforcer, that is, if reading the book increases the probability of the behavior which led to reading the book (assuming an appropriate state of deprivation).” (Psychology and Ideology: p.21).

This is a forced choice it is probable that there are some true claims in the book and some false claims in the book. The cause of us reading the book could be specified in various manners; being reinforced by reading that class of book in the past; a book recommendation from a friend whose recommendations in the past have been reinforcing. But Chomsky doesn’t ask what the cause of reading it is; he asks what the point of reading it. He says on Skinner’s central thesis, the only point of reading the book, is that it will modify behaviour. And it will only modify behaviour if it is a reinforcer, that is if reading the book increases the probability of the behaviour which led to reading the book (ibid p. 21). This is a strange interpretation of Skinner’s project. We have already discussed possible causes of reading the book. Possible consequences of reading the book are negative reinforcement; reading the book takes away boredom and increases the probability of reading more books like this in the future. Or the reader could be punished as a result of finding the book unintelligible, and excruciating to read, which will decrease the probability of reading books of this class in the future. Or the person could find the book positively reinforcing and this may lead to reading more books of this class and possible seeking a career in behavioural psychology.

            It is important to note that behavioural psychology doesn’t stand or fall based on what point each individual gets from reading one popular book by B.F. Skinner, there are now over a hundred years of behavioural research. And behavioural science should be evaluated on its own terms, which are the degree to which their principles have given us the ability to predict and control the behaviour of various organisms.

            Chomsky goes on to argue as follows:

“Consider the claim that reading the book might reinforce such behavior. Unfortunately, the claim is clearly false, if we use the term ‘reinforce’ with anything like its technical meaning. Recall that reading the book reinforces the desired behavior only if it is a consequence of the behavior; and obviously putting our fate in the hands of behavioural technologists is not behavior that led to (and hence can be reinforced by) reading Skinner’s book. Therefore, the claim can be true only if we deprive the term ‘reinforce’ of its technical meaning.” (Ibid p. 22)

Reading books in the past has been reinforced positively in our school and college environment. Doing so has led to reinforcing consequences in the past. Reading behavioural books in the past (Watson’s Psychology as the Behaviourist Views it), led Skinner to pursue a career in behaviourism, this has been reinforcing in terms of (discovering things which he finds reinforcing), and a long career (which he found reinforcing). Similarly, for us, the general public, reading in the past has been reinforced, if ‘Beyond Freedom and Dignity’ is in the stimulus class of popular science books people found reinforcing in the past then this may lead to people reading it. Lots of people reading it could influence behavioural change which will alter the probability of how people behave in the future. What courses they study, how they manage selection by consequences etc[1].

Chomsky’s critique though goes beyond the idea of reinforcing consequences of reading the Beyond, Freedom, and Dignity. He is also critical of Skinner’s casual manner of translating ordinary discourse into behaviourist language, and at the perceived lack of progress in behavioural science.

“Because of this unwillingness, there is also no discernible progress – today’s formulations in this domain are hardly different from those of 15 or 20 years ago – and no convincing refutation, for those who are untroubled by the fact that explanations can be invented on the spot, whatever the facts may be, within a system that is devoid of substance.” (Ibid pp 29-30)

Here it is fair to say Chomsky does have a point. Skinner had a penchant for inventing explanations for any behaviour or cognitive capacities in terms of reinforcement. And there was little indication that Skinner was overly concerned about testing the empirical validity of his claims about various complex behaviour being explicable in terms of reinforcement. Even today some behaviourists who have been heavily influenced by Skinner are critical of him for this tendency:

Evolution was for many years dramatically gene-centric…ontogenetic evolution was virtually ignored…behaviour analysis seemed to have made the opposite error…A good example is provided by the transcript of the recorded interview between B.F. Skinner and E.O. Wilson, in which almost every specialized, evolutionarily established behaviour put forward by Wilson was promptly interpreted by in Operant terms (Hayes and Sanford 2014 p. 115).

So, Chomsky’s criticism of Skinner casually translating every complex trait into something explicable in terms of operant conditioning is to the point. However, his criticism about a lack of advancement in behavioural science doesn’t stand up to critical scrutiny. Chomsky wrote ‘Ideology and Psychology’ in 1971 and his claim that there hadn’t been a huge advancement in behavioural science since around 1950 isn’t true.

             Behavioural science since 1950 had undergone rapid changes. Breland and Breland’s (1963) work on animal training demonstrated that instinctual drift would mean that non-human animals’ behaviour wasn’t as malleable as earlier naïve behaviourists thought. Skinner, who had long stressed both phylogenetic and ontogenetic factors playing a role in animal behaviour welcomed the work of the Breland’s. On Skinner’s way of thinking it was the behaviourists job to discover the different ways behaviour could be shaped and controlled through different schedules of reinforcement. The behaviourist wasn’t in the game of stipulating how malleable different organisms were. Nonetheless, despite the Breland’s work being congenial to Skinner’s behaviourism, for the public, instinctive drift made the thoughts of behaviourists gaining control over people and shaping their behaviour seem less threatening.

             As behavioural scientists continued to study human’s operating under schedules of reinforcement there was more reason to think that humans couldn’t be just shaped at a whim through schedules of reinforcement. Hundreds of behavioural studies on rule governed behaviour[2], have demonstrated that when humans were operating under rules this made them less sensitive to the contingencies of reinforcement. Children below the age of 5 could be shaped under schedules of reinforcement in a similar way to a rat, but once they passed 5 and could follow rules their behaviour became less sensitive to the contingencies of reinforcement (Bentall).

            Like the Breland’s work, work on rule-following sprung up from within behaviourism (Skinner 1963) and demonstrated that human behaviour was more complex than the behaviour of other organisms. The year Skinner wrote ‘Ideology and Psychology Sidman (1971) experimentally demonstrated that humans could derive untrained stimulus equivalence. And in the years since Steven Hayes (1989) demonstrated that humans could derive untrained relational frames (coordination, comparison, hierarchy, etc). The human under behavioural science began to closer resemble the human as described by cognitive scientists (built with innate constraints, have a species-specific capacity for productive reasoning etc), than it did the human as described by early behaviourists.  

Now Chomsky would parse some of these studies as resulting in the death of behaviourism as derived by Skinner.  However, things don’t have to be parsed in this manner. One could look at the work of behaviourists, such as Rescorla, Breland, Sidman, Lowe et all’s experimental refutations of previously held beliefs by behaviourists as a sign of an evolving healthy discipline.

One thing that should be emphasised was that when Skinner was writing ‘Beyond Freedom and Dignity’ work on rule following in behavioural science was being done which was already demonstrating that we couldn’t simply reinforce behaviours we wanted repeated, when people operated under verbal rules, they were less sensitive to the contingencies of reinforcement than non-verbal animals. Thus, even for behaviourists at the time Skinner wrote ‘Beyond Freedom and Dignity his work was outdated.  Society couldn’t be shaped in the manner Skinner wanted.

Chomsky goes on to quote Skinner’s claims about techniques we could use to control speech. Chomsky notes, correctly that Skinner’s science isn’t up to the task of doing such job. But he notes it would be abhorrent if such controls could be put in place:

Or consider freedom of speech. Skinner’s approach suggests that control of speech by direct punishment should be avoided, but that it is quite appropriate for speech to be controlled, say, by restricting good jobs to people who say what is approved by the designer of the culture. In accordance with Skinner’s ideas, these would be no violation of ‘academic freedom’ if promotions were granted only to those who conform, in their speech and writings, to the rules of the culture, though it would be wrong to go farther and punish those who deviate by saying what they believe to be true. Such deviants will simply remain in a state of deprivation. In fact, by giving people strict rules to follow, so that they know just what to say to be ‘reinforced’ by promotion, we will be ‘making the world safer’ and thus achieving the ends of behavioural technology (74,81). The literature of freedom would, quite properly, reject and abhor such controls. (Ibid pp. 30-31).

What Chomsky doesn’t note though is that Skinner’s philosophy always had safeguards in place so those under control had a means to resist any science of behavioural engineering.

            Since 1953 Skinner had written about countercontrol as a way organisms had of resisting being controlled by others. Spencer et al (2022) define countercontrol as follows:

“Countercontrol is a Skinnerian Operant concept that posits that an individual’s attempts to exert control over another person’s behaviour may evoke a countercontrolling response from the person being controlled that functions to avoid or escape potentially aversive conditions generated by the controller.” (Spencer et al p. 457)

Skinner had targeted our notion that people are free. He argued that people only described themselves as free when they could not identify the variables which were controlling their behaviour. He also noted that when people are under the control of positive reinforcers, they often describe their behaviour as freely chosen. He gave the example of state lottery which works as an implicit tax on people and noted that people think they freely chose to do the lottery. He emphasised the point that people value freedom because it is controlled by positive reinforcement and as a result does not occasion countercontrol (Delprato 2002 p. 195).

            Skinner warned that evidence of lack of countercontrol as an indication of “freedom” was dangerous. Belief that we are freely acting can lead to inadvertently being subject to long term aversive consequences resulting from our behaviour. This can happen when the controller is aware of these long-term consequences and the controlee is the ultimate loser in this scenario (ibid p. 195).

            Skinner argues that the correct solution to control is not to abolish it (he thinks this is impossible), but to analyse it and see if this is the type of control and consequence we want and if not to figure out a different type of controlling system to work within:

“Humans need (a) to eliminate aversive control (often a practical impossibility), (b) to identify positive reinforcement and other inconspicuous forms of control that have deferred aversive consequences, and (c) to substitute positive reinforcement contingencies without such consequences.” (Delprato p. 196).

Delprato argues that the above sequence is practically impossible, so we are in effect stuck with the use of countercontrol.

            As we discussed above since the mid-sixties, we knew that once people begin to follow verbal rules their behaviour isn’t shaped by the contingencies of reinforcement in the same way as non-human behaviour. Nonetheless, control and counter control are still facts in any society we live in. Relational Frame Theorists, behaviourists who have been studying emergent properties of verbal behaviour, have recently tried to tie countercontrol in with derived relational responding to see if we could use the concept now that our understanding of rule-following behaviour has expanded beyond Skinner’s conception (Spencer et al 2022).

            As things stand 50 years after Skinner wrote his ‘Beyond Freedom and Dignity’ we still are nowhere near developing the capacity to behaviourally engineer our society. While Chomsky sometimes caricatured Skinner’s behaviourist position. He was surely correct to note that Skinner’s proclamations about the capacities of behavioural science to engineer our culture went well beyond anything possible in 1971 or anything possible today.


[1] I am not hear arguing that we can explain people reading books entirely in terms of reinforcement, I am merely demonstrating that Chomsky’s quick argument for incoherence doesn’t work.

[2] See for example: Weiner et al (1964), Lippman and Myer (1967), Lowe et al (1983), Hayes et al (1986).

Are large language models the intellectual ancestors of Behaviorism

Childers et al 2023 argue that the debate between Chomsky and Quine and Skinner is revisited by contemporary debates on Large Language Models and Chomskian linguistics. They go on to argue that proponents of the view that data driven large language models mirror human natural language make the same mistakes that Chomsky critiqued people like Quine and Skinner ago 50 years ago. In this blog post I will argue that Childers et al largely misinterpret Skinner and Quine’s project and hence any connections they draw with Large Language Models and Connectionism are problematic.

            Childers et al argue that Quine and Skinner’s empiricism has collapsed under criticisms from Chomsky. And that Quine responded to this collapse by modifying his position his empiricism to accommodate Chomsky’s position by appealing to innate mechanisms.  They note that once such an appeal accepted then we are in a place where we are no longer empiricists, and our position is closer to that of rationalists. I would argue that this is an idiosyncratic reading of empiricism. Empiricists, like Hume and Locke, appealed to innate mechanisms explain how we acquired our knowledge of the world. It is just that the innate mechanisms they appealed to wouldn’t be sufficient to account for the complexity of human language and cognition. Quine’s externalized empiricism is of a piece with Hume’s except for in Quine’s case he is advocating for the innate mechanisms to be determined experimentally. Childers et al call this hybridised empiricism and note that it is empiricism only in name. It is unclear to me why Quine arguing that we determine what innate structures are necessary based on behavioural tests should be considered anything other than ordinary empiricism externalized.

            They do go on to make the further point that Quine’s speculations about the innate principles necessary are extremely vague. I would agree with them on this point; when Quine talks about analogical synthesis being the method in which we connect sentences with sentences he is extremely vague. Gibson (1987) wrote about Quine’s postulation of analogical synthesis being a postulated innate structure to be mapped by future scientists. In the 35 years since Gibson wrote those words there has been very little work done by philosophers influenced by Quine filling in the details of this project.

            There has though been scientific research into analogy from a scientific perspective in both behavioural science and cognitive science. Relational Frame Theorists are behavioural scientists whose experimental work on language has left them to abandon some of Skinner’s account of language. Thus, they argue their research shows that rule following in language changes how people respond to schedules of reinforcement, and they argue that human specific emergent properties such as the ability to derive stimulus equivalence, and relations of coordination, hierarchy, etc. These relational frames under contextual control exhibit the property of Mutual entailment, combinatorial entailment, and transfer of function (Relational Frame Theory an Overview p.62). In Relational Frame Theory they demonstrated empirically that analogy is a relational frame which typically emerges at about 5 years of age, defining analogy as the capacity to derive sameness amongst equivalence relations or equivalence-equivalence responding.  They think that these derived relational frames may play a role in linguistic productivity. However, it would be unfair to argue that they vindicate Quine’s concept of analogical synthesis as Quine’s vague formulations played no role in the experimental paradigm. And furthermore, it is impossible to tell the degree to which RFT is consistent with Quine as his formulations were too vague to match on to them.

            In cognitive science analogical reasoning has been researched in detail see for example Hofstadter (2013), and Gentre and Hoyos (2017). Gentre has being doing experimental work on analogies for over 40 years. Based on her experimental work she argues that children start deriving analogies from 7months of age. The discrepancy between her chronology of when analogies are acquired and the timeline in RFT can be accounted for in the lower criteria set for what counts as an analogy for Gentre. Gentre argues that analogies involve transfer of knowledge from one area to another whereas RFT theorists argue that stimulus-stimulus equivalence is necessary for something to count as analogy.

            In their ‘Analogy and Abstraction’ Gentner and Hoyos note a difficulty in explaining children’s acquiring of abstract analogies and their difficulty is like the one which faces Quine. We know from the psychological literature that children (1) prefer to extend their concepts based on bare perceptual similarities, (2) this results in them making concrete analogies, (3) children can extend their comparison classes through multiple exemplars.

Two of the primary ways of making an analogy are through projective alignment and through mutual alignment. Projective alignment is when people use an already well understood domain to illuminate another domain. However, when it comes to young children, they do not have a large store of well understood concepts, so it is difficult for them to use already understood concepts to explain a different concept. Therefore, young children typically use mutual alignment in their analogical abstraction. In mutual alignment analogies one discovers commonalities which were not obvious in either analog (ibid p. 3). Mutual alignment involves establishing a structural alignment between two-representations based on matching relations between analogues (ibid p.4).

The difficulty is to explain how children can go from using concrete analogies based on bare perceptual similarities to more abstract relational concepts. One problem is that presenting young children with exemplars which are not perceptually similar will not be helpful as the children won’t have the capacity to mutually align the two analogs. So, we are left with a mystery as to how young children form more abstract relational analogs. Gentner and Hoyos argue that we overcome this barrier through a process called progressive alignment. Experimental studies have shown that if young children are presented with abstract relational analogues they cannot pick up on the relationship. However, if they are first trained on concrete analogues and then later retested on the abstract relational analogues their performance improves dramatically.

This progressive alignment gives young children the capacity to move beyond bare similarity and acquire more abstract relations. Like in the case of RFT it is possible to use these experimental works to fill out Quine’s speculations, however, given the vagueness of Quine’s speculations it would be a stretch to call this work Quinean. Thus, I would agree with Childers et al that Quine’s notion of similarity and analogy is too vague to do the work he set for himself.

When it comes to Skinner, Childers et al err two major ways. Firstly, they argue that Skinner’s Verbal Behaviour book would be unheard of today if it wasn’t connected in people’s mind with Quine’s empiricist model. However, Skinner’s Verbal Behaviour has in fact spawned a massive experimental literature with hundreds of experimental studies into Skinner’s Verbal Operants (Sauter and Leblanc 2006, Jennings et al 2021). At first research inspired by Skinner focused on simpler verbal operants such as Mands and Tacts with a lot of research being applied research with people with developmental disabilities (Ochs and Dixon 1989). But over the last 15 years there has been an explosion of research into more complex verbal operants such as the intraverbal, and there is a massive increase in non-applied experiments and studies of people without an intellectual disability or autism (over 50% of the people studied have no diagnosis) (Jennings et al 2021). As the years go by the pace of experimental tests into Skinner’s Verbal Operants are rapidly increasing (Aguirre et al 2016).  There is no evidence, or reason to think, that any of this research was inspired by Skinner’s name being associated with Quine. In fact Quine’s name is virtually never cited in papers on Verbal Behaviour, or in papers about behavioural off shoots from Verbal Behaviour.

Secondly, Kenneth McCorquodale (1970), replied to Chomsky’s review of Skinner’s Verbal Behaviour and noted that when Chomsky criticized Skinner’s notion of the probability of a Tact occurring, he confused the probability of a tact being used in a particular moment, versus the probability of a Tact being used at any point in a person’s life McCorquodale (1970). Childers et al criticised the use of the notion of “momentary probability” as an idiosyncratic use of probability and went on to make the following point:

. “More importantly, his claim that under certain circumstances the relevant probability becomes “extremely high” is unwarranted, unless we already know how the language functions.” (Childers et al p. 221).

It is unclear precisely what Childers et al mean by “under certain circumstances”. One circumstance could be in studies on intraverbal acquisition. If a child is being taught to use an intraverbal, using multi-exemplar training involving the frame “the wheels on the bus go_”, what would the probability of a child saying “round and round”? Are Childers et al seriously suggesting that we cannot estimate the probability cannot be established in these circumstances? And given that we have established developmental milestones on things like stimulus equivalence and the training procedures used to elicit them are Childers et al seriously suggesting that we cannot assign probabilities in these experimental settings? Granted Chomsky’s point still stands, it is probably not possible to assign probabilities to certain words being spoken as people interact daily, but has little bearing on experimental control in precise settings which is what Skinner and Relational Frame Theorists were interested in.

            Ultimately what Childers et al argue is that both Quine and Skinner had to do in response to Chomsky’s criticisms is to progressively modify their positions with more and more innate architecture. There is little evidence to support this interpretation of Quine, see Gibson (1987), for a detailed exposition of the extended debate between Quine and Chomsky on innate architecture. However, I largely agree with Childers et al that Quine’s vague sketch of analogical synthesis wasn’t detailed enough or clear enough to account for our linguistic development. This is important because Quine was committed to giving a mechanistic explanation for our behavioural capacities. He argued consistently throughout his career that it is ultimately at the neurological level we should be looking for our explanations, that behaviour was just data to point us towards underlying mechanisms. If the data turned out to support a Chomskian type architecture I don’t think it would have much difference to Quine’s overall project of naturalizing epistemology.

            Skinner on the other hand was interested in discovering behavioural regularities. He was interested in underlying neuroscientific explanations only insofar as they helped in functional control of the organism in particular circumstances. Whether people are impressed with the literature inspired by Skinner’s verbal behaviour and the predictions it makes is one thing. But this literature needs to be engaged with we cannot stipulate a priori how much experimental control has been gained in a particular experimental setting. As things stand there is little evidence that empirical evidence that Skinner’s account will ever be able to handle linguistic productivity[1]. And this will make it extremely difficult to ever gain predictive control over more complex linguistic behaviour beyond Tacts, Mands and simple Intraverbals. Behaviourists inspired by Skinner such as Relational Frame Theorists claim that they can handle linguistic productivity but since there is little engagement with linguistic data it is hard to test these claims. Ultimately these behaviourist studies are engaged in tests of how the organism behaves not stipulating the nature of the organism’s brain. The historical story Childers et al tell of Quine, Skinner and Chomsky’s dispute being mirrored in contemporary debates on connectionism, Large Language Models, and standard computational theories. The work of Quine and Skinner are very different from each other and both of their views have very little in common with work ongoing in Artificial Intelligence.


[1] See David C Palmer 2023 ‘Towards a Behavioural Interpretation of English Grammar’ for a recent Skinnerian inspired attempt at understand grammar behaviourally.

The Extended Mind and Intellectual Disability.

The Extended Mind is a thesis by Andy Clark and David Chalmers which states that the Mind Extends beyond the brain and encompasses aspects of the physical world. They give an example of a person who has dementia who keeps a diary to remind him of things he needs to do, such as when to take medication, where things are stored etc. If the person with dementia has reliable access to this diary most of the time, then they argue that the information in the diary is part of his extended mind.

            In ordinary circumstances if I want to remember when to do something it is because the information is stored in my brain, and I can access to information to make decisions. I don’t have to always have access to the information sometimes I may forget, but in general I have reliable access to the information. Chalmers and Clark argue that it is arbitrary to consider the information stored in a brain which you can reliably access to be part of your mind but to think that information in your diary which you can reliably access isn’t.

The thesis is counter intuitive. And some people reject it because of this counterintuitive feel, arguing that the thesis extends our ordinary concept of cognition too far. However, this counter argument has little force. There is little reason to assume that our theoretical understanding of a particular phenomena should be intuitive at first. Logical coherence should be the test of the theory not whether it chimes with your folk-psychological concepts.

The argument of Chalmers and Clark focused on information within a diary, but today with our phones which we carry everywhere with us storing so much information, the argument becomes even more radical, with it implying that aspects of the internet that we can reliably access are part of our extended mind.

Intellectual Disability

Psychologist J.J Gibson wrote about affordances which are relational aspects of our environment which we could interact with. Affordances relate not just to features of the environment but to the suitability of the environment to an observer or agent. Thus, steep stairs are an affordance for a person who can walk but to a person in a wheelchair they are not an affordance. Our natural and social environments contain affordances for some people but not for all. What are affordances are depends on the intentions, capabilities, and interests of the individual. In general, we tend to build our environment in such a way that can help people access the affordances they need, for example, building wheelchair ramps.

People with an intellectual disability who are non-verbal have interests and desires, but as a result of being non-verbal they will have difficulties in accessing various affordances in their environment. It is for this reason that there are practices and regulations in place which ensure that organisations who care for people with an intellectual disability do everything possible to ensure that they facilitate their communication capacities. Doing this involves giving them access to Speech and language therapists, occupational therapists, and a full Multi-Disciplinary Team. Furthermore, staff working with them must be trained in things like techniques to facilitate non-verbal people communicating their needs. Various types of augmentative communication devices are used on the recommendations of SLT, and things are in place such as visual schedules and Picture Exchange Communication System (an augmentative system based on Skinners Verbal Behaviour).

We saw above when discussing the patient with dementia who had reliable access to his diary that this could be considered a part of his extended mind. In the case of a non-verbal person in a service, there are affordances in their environment they may want to access such as going for coffee, visiting friends, going for a bus drive etc. If they can use PECS cards to indicate what they want, and those cards are not reliably available they you are taking away a part of their extended mind. It would be analogous to taking away a person’s prosthetic leg. A prosthetic leg may be artificial, but it is still a part of the persons way of accessing affordances in their environment and the same thing would apply to augmentative communicative systems.

I would argue that a similar thing is true of staff working with non-verbal people in a service. The staffing team ends up as part of the extended mind of the non-verbal person they are supporting. Just like the diary of the person with dementia contains information he can access, and my I-phone contains information I can access, staff working with non-verbal people with an intellectual disability contain information and affordances which a non-verbal person cannot access on their own.

As discussed above, not providing a person with reliable access to their prosthetic leg, denies them access to affordances in their environment, and likewise not providing a non-verbal person with experienced staff who know them and are versed in communication training is denying them affordances in their environment. It is for this reason that there is such a massive push in policies to ensure that effective communication training is available, consistent staffing are maintained etc. However, in a lot of the literature this is spelled out in atomistic terms. Thinking of these issues in terms of the extended mind helps people think  more relationally, and emphasises how our environment, social network, and social supports are partially constitutive of our own minds.

Quine on the Interdependence of Mands and Tacts.

In this blogpost I will consider Quine’s relation to two of B.F. Skinner’s Verbal Operants: the Mand, and the Tact. I will argue that Quine’s Observation Sentence is analogous to Skinner’s Tact, but that Quine makes very little use of the notion of a Mand. A Mand is one of the most studied verbal operants, and it is the first verbal operants that is targeted by behavioural scientists if a child is experiencing language delays. Yet Quine gives the Mand a very small role in his overall theory of language acquisition. I will discuss Quine’s reasons for not considering things like Manding as important in sketching his naturalized epistemology and then discuss the degree to which these verbal operants are separable and how their separability will affect Quine’s choice of downplaying of the role of Mand’s in his story of how we go from stimulus-to science.

Quine’s Relation to Empirical Psychology

While Quine didn’t use the same vocabulary as Skinner some of his concepts map effortlessly onto Skinner’s concepts. Thus, Quine’s notion of an Observation Sentence is the same as Skinner’s notion of a Tact (both are shaped by discriminative stimulus and social feedback). Nonetheless despite arguing for this functional independence between different Verbal Operants Skinner noted that for ordinary speakers the two may be entwined. Thus, if a person has acquired a label as a Tact the chances are that they will be able to use it as a Mand. Skinner gives four reasons to support his argument for interdependence. (1) Tact emergence may be facilitated by the acquisition of a Mand in the presence of the Manded stimulus. (2) The similarity between the stimulus that evokes a Tact and that that evokes a Man may be similar enough to affect a transfer. (3) Transfer may occur if care givers reinforce one operant as if it were the other, (4) Children early in life may acquire generalized verbal skills which result in both the Mand, and the Tact being acquired (Petursdottir et all p.60). Skinner was speculating about these matters but in the 60 years since he wrote ‘Verbal Behaviour’ their partial interdependence has been confirmed.

Quine showed no interest in Mand’s and hence he had little interest in how Mand’s and Tacts related to each other and affected the process of acquiring a language.  He was clear that because of his interest in ontology and epistemology he was giving an idealized conception of how we acquire language. He was interested in observation sentences because they are our entering wedge into language and hence to our theory of the world. He is explicit that the story he gives of how we go from stimulus to science is meant to be an impressionistic one. He fully acknowledges that his story may deviate from the story told by a fully worked out science.

            Quine’s position on this matter is dubious. He was critical of Carnap for engaging in make belief in place of making use of current scientific psychology.

“But why all this creative reconstruction, all this make belief? The stimulation of his sensory receptors is all anybody has to go on, ultimately, in arriving at his picture of the world. Why not see how this reconstruction really proceeds? Why not settle for empirical psychology?” (Epistemology Naturalised p. 74)

 Yet Quine himself is in effect engaged in a made-up story about how we go from stimulus to science. He justifies this as follows:

“Much of what is earliest and most urgent in language learning, furthermore, is a matter of neither stating nor assenting nor acting upon statements, but of importuning…But statement learning is what is relevant to our study, which aims at understanding the acquisition of scientific theory.” (The Roots of Reference p. 46)

“Anyway, I am not bent even upon a factual account of the learning of English, welcome though it would be. My concern is with the essential psychogenesis of reference would be fulfilled in fair measure with a plausible account of how one might proceed from infancy step by step to a logically regimented language of science, even bypassing English” (Ibid p. 92)

 Because of Quine’s emphasis on cognitive language, he is ignoring the messier pragmatic aspects of learning a language that are described by people such as the later Wittgenstein, and Skinner. There is a sense in which we can justify this; it is after all standard practice in the sciences to engage in idealizations. Quine could be parsed as sketching a scientific story of how we go from stimulus to science; we can use this abstract sketch and fill in the details as we learn more about the acquisition process. Nonetheless, Quine does seem to be guilty of holding Carnap to higher standards than he holds himself to.

Because Quine is only interested in descriptive language and its role in us acquiring our theory of the world; he claims he doesn’t need to think about things such as importuning or as Skinner would it Manding.  Skinner had noted that Mands such as asking for water would be controlled by an establishment operation of a deprivation such as thirst and subsequent reinforcement of the thirst being relieved, while the Tact for Water could be controlled by a non-verbal discriminative stimulus, which the person was reinforced for saying the word in the presence of. Thus, you would have two different operants controlling the one sound for ‘Water’. As we saw above Skinner thought that these two operants would in practice end up entwined. If indeed Mands and Tacts are intertwined, then this would affect any proposed psychologically realistic story of how we go from stimulus to science.

Lamarre and Holand (1985) did a study on children tested the independence Tacts and Mands with preschool children. They trained children up on the relations “on the left” and “on the right” as both Mands and as Tacts. The study found that when the children learned them as Tacts, they couldn’t generalize them to Mands without training, while when they learned them as Mand’s they couldn’t generalize them to Tacts without training. This indicated that the two terms were for young children at first functionally independent and that transfer from one to the other wasn’t automatic.

Lamarre and Holland’s original study has been criticised by Wallace et al 2006. They noted that Lamarre and Holland’s establishing operations may not have been clear. There is no indication whether the items the child is manding for or the reinforcement they are receiving for Manding are items the child desires. When this was controlled for in other experiments the transfer from Tacts to Mands occurred for preferred items. Wallace et al claim their study demonstrates how responses taught as Tacts can facilitate the establishment of Mands for high preference items. And they noted that their experiments showed a difficulty with Tact-to-Mand transfer for low preference items (in line with Lamarre and Hollands study). Demonstrating that their lack of transfer was more than likely caused by not using sufficiently motivating reinforcers.

Gamba et al (2016) have done a meta-analysis on studies into whether functional independence in Mand-Tact independence has been demonstrate empirically. And they noted that there has been 28 empirical studies into the functional independence of the Mand and the Tact since Lamarre and Holland’s original study. They noted that there have been 13 studies which have demonstrated the functional independence of Mands and Tacts, but that in studies which the stimuli tacted and Manded were preferred items transfer of function occurred (Gamba et al p.27). Whether these studies are sufficient to cast doubt on the functional independence of the Mand and Tact is hard open to interpretation. Gamba et al note that in some of these experiments the Manded items were present which may have served to evoke previous Tacts and this may need to be controlled for in future experiments (ibid p. 31).

Thus far the experimental results are not sufficient to conclusively demonstrate the functional independence of Mand’s and Tacts. Quine appears to have been agnostic on this issue. However, one questions whether he has a right to this agnosticism. He was critical of Carnap for engaging in make belief in his epistemology, but his own Naturalized Epistemology engages in as much make belief. Quine’s focus on observation sentences at the expense of things like Mand’s serves to distort our picture of how we acquire our language and scientific heritage. In abstracting away from these details Quine is giving a hyper-intellectual fantasy of how we acquire language he is letting the metaphor of the scientist being a disinterested theorist keying observation sentences to stimuli, blind him to the more pragmatic aspects of language acquisition.

In this blogpost I discussed Quine’s relation to Skinner’s Verbal Operants of Mands and Tacts. In my next post I will focus on linking Quine’s concept of association of sentences to sentences with recent empirical work on Skinner’s Verbal Operant the Intraverbal.

Skinner, Quine, and Contextual Behavioural Science: Pragmatism vs Mechanism

                                                       Introduction

In this blogpost I will discuss the relation between Quine and Skinner on the issue of postulating hypothetical neural entities to explain behaviour. I will argue that Quine’s mechanistic position is at odds with Skinner’s radical behaviourism. While Skinner’s position is pragmatic and focuses on whole organism environmental relations; Quine is only interested in how we can use external behaviour as a way of guiding us towards underlying neural mechanisms. I then argue that despite situating himself in the behavioural camp Quine’s views are closer to those of contemporary cognitive scientists.

            Having discussed Quine’s relation with Skinner on the above issue I then move on to discuss an analogous debate between contextual behavioural scientists inspired by Skinner and theorists such as Eva Jablonka. This debate indicates that Quine and Skinner’s disagreement is not a mere academic debate from the history of the philosophy of science but is a live debate in contemporary evolutionary theory and behavioural science. The position of Skinner and Contextual Behavioural Scientists is a minority position in the philosophy of science. However, both Skinner and Contextual Behavioural Scientists have come up with concrete empirical results using their minority philosophy of science. It is an open empirical question whether they could have made similar discoveries using standard mechanistic philosophical assumptions.

                                                   Quine’s Mechanism

Quine was a philosopher and was primarily interested in issues in logic, epistemology, and ontology. As his philosophical world view grew, his emphasis was on explaining all these subjects naturalistically. Quine wasn’t a psychologist or a linguist. But his naturalism led him to the point where he argued that epistemology was a branch of empirical psychology. So, in working out his epistemology he needed to engage in psychological speculations as well as appeal to empirical data from psychology. Likewise, since Quine recognised the importance of language in our ability to acquire our theory of the world, he needed a theory to explain how we acquired our language. Quine described his position on these matters as behaviouristic. In psychology he argued one may or may not be a behaviourist. But in linguistics one had to be behaviouristic because in acquiring language we relied on intersubjective keying of sounds to objects as we communicated with our socio-linguistic community.

            But it is important to note that Quine’s brand of behaviourism was mechanistic. In a sense Quine’s behaviourism was closer to that of earlier behaviourists such as Watson and Pavlov who used behavioural tests to hypothesize about underlying neurological mechanisms. Whereas Skinner and the behaviourist’s who followed him in his radical behaviourist philosophy held a very different view. They were interested in prediction and control of the whole organism in a variety of different contexts. Skinner for example was critical of what he viewed as premature appeal to hypothetical neurological mechanisms by scientists like Watson. He argued that these hypothetical neurological mechanisms were premature given the fact we hadn’t done sufficient behavioural tests to understand behaviour itself.

            In fact, Skinner went further than the above he also argued that the behaviourist would become interested in physiology once it could be used as an aid in the prediction and control of whole organisms in their environment. Skinner, unlike Quine, didn’t think that the true or deeper explanation was to be provided at the physiological level. Rather Skinner believed that physiology would eventually be a relevant tool in predicting and controlling the organism when acting in its environment. Physiology would be part of the behavioural stream not its underlying detached cause.

            In his paper “Jacques Loeb, B. F Skinner, and the Legacy of Prediction and Control” (1995). Hackenberg analysed how Skinner’s views on prediction and control developed. Hackenberg nicely sums up Skinner’s views on neuroscience below:

“Until physiological events could enter into effective action via the direct prediction and control of behavior, they would remain part of what Skinner (1938) called “the conceptual nervous system” and what Loeb called “the mysticism of the ganglion cells” (Loeb, 1890/1905, p. 114).” (Hackenberg 1995 p.228).

This shows a sharp distinction between Skinner and Quine’s views on this topic. Skinner did argue that physiology would become more important once we got our behavioural facts in order. But he also argued that the behaviourist would become interested in physiology once it could be used as an aid in the prediction and control of whole organisms in their environment. Skinner, unlike Quine, didn’t think that the true or deeper explanation was to be provided at the physiological level. Rather Skinner believed that physiology would eventually be a relevant tool in predicting and controlling the organism when acting in its environment. Physiology would be part of the behavioural stream not its underlying detached cause. Skinner is very clear on his views on this subject:

“When we have achieved a practical control over the organism, theories of behavior lose their point. In representing and managing relevant variables, a conceptual model is useless; we come to grips with behavior itself. When behavior shows order and consistency, we are much less likely to be concerned with physiological or mentalistic causes. (p. 231)”[1]

As can be seen Skinner’s views on physiology are that in so far as it is a useful tool in the prediction and control of the organism, we can appeal to it. But he is less interested in postulating neurological mechanisms to explain the behaviour of organisms. Quine’s views on this topic are very different than Skinners. One of the primary reasons for this divergence is that Quine is interested in explanation of behaviour not just prediction and control.

                                            Quine on Hypothetical Entities

            Throughout his career Quine has been censorious in relation to superfluous appeals to hypothetical entities. Thus, Quine has criticized appeals to meanings, ideas, and propositions to explain linguistic behaviour. His reason for criticizing these notions is that he thinks that they are shadowy notions which distract us from looking at actual behaviour in concrete circumstances. But Quine has shown less misgivings about hypothetical structures when it comes to postulating neurological structures as an explanation of behaviour. Quine has specified on numerous occasions that the thinks that the deeper level of explanations are to be found at the neurological level not at the behavioural level.

            Quine is explicit about this when it comes to the notion of a disposition. When an organism has a disposition to engage in certain behaviours in certain circumstances Quine thinks we should aim to cash out these dispositions neurologically eventually. In the meantime, we should think of dispositions as hypothetical neurological states:[2]

“Each disposition, in my view, is a physical state or mechanism… Where the general dispositional idiom has its use is as follows. By means of it we can refer to a hypothetical state or mechanism that we do not yet understand, or to any of various such states or mechanisms, while merely specifying one of its characteristic effects, such as dissolution upon immersion in water.” (ibid p.10)

Quine’s use of the dispositional idiom set him and Chomsky at odds. Quine had defined language as a “complex of dispositions to verbal behaviour” . Chomsky rejected this definition because he argued that disposition used in the above sense meant that we could specify the probability of a word being used in a certain circumstance. And Chomsky argued that it is senseless to speak of the probability of a word being spoken on a random occasion. Quine argued that he was speaking of the probability of a word being spoken in a particular circumstance of query and assent. Language is an incredibly complex phenomenon. We still don’t have a clear understanding of the probability of a sentence being spoken in concrete circumstances. So, it may help us understand the notion of disposition in terms of a simpler organism in a tightly controlled experimental setting.

            If we take a Pigeon in a Skinner box who has the box tailor made to his size and who is typically operating at 80% of its ad lib weight (Fester and Skinner p. 29). And we put it on a fixed interval ratio schedule of reinforcement for pecking at lights of a particular hue. We will end up with curve which is predictive of the Pigeons behaviour under this schedule of reinforcement. This can be cashed out in the dispositional terms; Pigeon W in a state of deprivation X has a disposition to peck in way Y under schedule of reinforcement Z[3]. Here we have a real behavioural regularity (albeit in an artificially contrived environment), and it is instructive to think about how Quine would handle this case.

            When discussing solubility of salt in water Quine argued that this disposition of salt to be soluble in water ultimately needs to be cashed out in terms of underlying physical structures for us have a proper explanation of it. Quine would presumably make the same argument when it comes to Pigeon’s pecking behaviour under a schedule of reinforcement. Skinner’s difficulty with jumping straight to physiological mechanisms was that it was premature and was done prior to us getting our behavioural facts in order. So, for example, when theorists such as Watson were postulating hypothetical neural mechanisms to explain reinforcement they were doing so in ignorance of the distinction between operant and classical conditioning. Furthermore, they were doing so in ignorance of the distinction of various schedules of reinforcement and how they effect behaviour. So, Skinner would have argued that their hypotheses were radically premature, we would be better served by continuing to map out behavioural dispositions under various schedules of reinforcement. Rather than simply postulating a mechanism the instant we discover a regularity.

            Skinner does think that we will eventually be capable of advancing our understanding of human behaviour through neuroscience. But he argues that this will be achieved through understanding how the brain physically changes when undergoing schedules of reinforcement not through speculative hypothesis:

“The physiologist of the future will tell us all that can be known about what is happening inside the behaving organism. His account will be an important advance over a behavioural analysis because the latter is necessarily “historical”-that is to say, it is confined to functional relations showing temporal gaps. Something done today which affects the behaviour of the organism tomorrow. No matter how clearly that fact can be established, as step is missing, and we must supply it. He will be able to show how an organism is changed when exposed to contingencies of reinforcement and why the changed organism then behaves in a different way, possibly at a much later date. What he discovers cannot invalidate the laws of a science of behaviour, but it will make the picture of human action more nearly complete.  (About Behaviourism pp.236-237)

Skinner’s emphasis on “knowing what is happening inside the behaving organism”, is important. He has no problem with discoveries about the underlying neuroscience which explains the behaviour of the organism in terms of schedules of reinforcement. What he disagrees with is explanations in terms of hypothetical mechanisms.

Skinner argues that appeal to hypothetical entities to explain behaviour amount to what he calls the conceptual nervous system. His criticisms of Pavlov invariably involved chastising him for invoking conceptual analogues for the nervous system which had no neurological reality:

The subtitle of his Conditioned Reflexes is ‘An investigation of the Physiological Activity of the Cerebral Cortex,’ but no direct observations of the cortex are reported. The data given are quite obviously concerned with the behavior of reasonably intact dogs, and the only nervous system of which he speaks is the conceptual one. (Skinner, 1938, p. 427).

As we mentioned above Quine could be accused of to some degree adopting positions analogous to Pavlov’s conceptual nervous system.

            When Quine speaks of hypothetical mechanisms some of his talk would be innocuous from Skinner’s point of view. Thus, when Quine speaks of “…a disposition is a promissory note for an eventual description in mechanical terms” (The Roots of Reference p. 14), there can be little objection. All he is arguing is that dispositional states have underlying physical states. This is an uncontroversial position. But when Quine begins arguing for hypothetical mechanisms to explain perceptual similarity and receptual similarity (ibid p. 18), and claims that postulating such mechanisms is unavoidable (ibid p.24). He is moving into the realm of arguing for a conceptual nervous system. Quine argues that such hypothetical mechanisms are on a par with positing things like genes on hypothetical grounds with the aim being to discover their physical properties later (ibid p. 27).  

            Despite calling himself a behaviourist, Quine’s discussions of hypothetical mechanisms to explain overt behaviour puts him closer to positions advocated by cognitive scientists (of both a connectionist and computationalist perspective) than it does to behaviourists like Skinner[4]. This dispute between both is largely a philosophical one. It depends on the interests of the researcher. Is the prediction and control of an organism in different contexts the key to a science of behaviour or is giving a mechanistic and reductionistic account of more importance?

                                                The Sins of the Father

            In this section we will see how the contemporary disagreement with Jablonka (2018) and Dougher and Hamilton (2018) on the issue of mechanistic postulations mirrors the disagreement between Quine and Skinner. This contemporary debate indicates that the issues between Quine and Skinner are live issues in the philosophy of behavioural science.

In Dougher and Hamilton’s (2018) paper“The Contextual Science of Learning: Integrating Behavioural and Evolution Science Within a Functional Approach”[5] they attempt to integrate Contextual Behavioural Science[6] with Evolutionary science. CBS operates within the Skinnerian pragmatic whole organism philosophy which we discussed above. While scientists in CBS claim to have gone beyond Skinner in many respects empirically, their underlying philosophy is very similar to Skinner’s radical behaviourism.

Dougher and Hamilton integrate evolutionary theory and CBS in the context of learning theory. They focus on research into spatial learning, contrasting mechanistic versus functional accounts of spatial learning. They argue that mechanism was an intellectual ancestor of positivism, the hypothetic-deductive account of science, and methodological behaviourism (ibid p. 16). Following Palmer (1994) they label mechanism an inferred process approach (ibid p. 16). This approach involves using behavioural data to draw inferences about underlying neurological or cognitive mechanisms and appeal to these mechanisms as the causal factors that produce the behaviour. This approach typically involves studying groups of organisms and drawing out statistical facts about these groups to produce mechanistic hypotheses which they hold onto until some prediction fails, or experimental data refutes the hypothesis (ibid p. 16).

            Functionalism instead of looking for hypothesised learning mechanisms take the behaviour of the whole organism in relation to its historical and immediate environmental context as the subject matter to be studied (ibid p.16). They look for explanations of behaviour (defined through its antecedents and consequences) in the functional relation between the behaviour and its environmental contexts (ibid p. 16). Because of the heavy emphasis they place on prediction and control they focus their attention on behavioural studies of individuals acting in context. They achieve their generalized results through replication across participants (ibid p. 17). They parse the primary difference between both approaches as follows:

“From the dominant mechanistic perspective, learning is typically defined as changes in an organism resulting from experience…. a functional definition of learning as an ontogenetic adaptation. The emphasis here is not on the organism or its internal mechanisms but on the observed functional regularities between behaviour and environments.” (Ibid p.17)

                                              Spatial Learning

They discuss O Keefe and Nadel’s (1978) work on cognitive mapping theory of the hippocampus[7], and use this as a paradigm example of a mechanistic approach. They don’t argue that O Keefe and Nadel’s work is incorrect, acknowledging that work is still on going on the overall project. However, they point out that Hamilton, Rosenfelt, and Whishaw (2004) have done experimental work on stimulus functions which operate throughout spatial navigation trials (ibid p. 18):

“Results showed that distinct segments of navigation toward a goal location depended on different environmental stimuli, with the initial selection of a direction based on more global features of the environment and subsequent/terminal aspects of the trip based on stimuli located at or near a goal. Thus, fine grain functional relations are operating in spatial navigation.” (Ibid p. 18).

They argue even if one is a mechanist, one should be on the lookout for functional relations before automatically appealing to inferred entities.

Dougherty and Hamilton’s paper was published in Sloan-Wilson and Hayes (eds) Evolution and Conceptual Behavioural Science. And at the end of their chapter in a section called “Dialogue on Learning”, they a discussion with one of the other authors in the book Eva Jablonka. In Eva Jablonka’s paper “Classical and Operant Conditioning: Evolutionarily Distinct Strategies?” (co-authored with Bronfman and Ginsburg) she discussed evolutionary origins of operant and classical conditioning arguing that we couldn’t definitively argue that they were separate mechanisms. She argued that both operant and classical conditioning are intertwined and can be explained with a mechanism called limited association which evolved during the Cambrian Explosion and may have been responsible for the unprecedented diversity of species at that time.

When commenting on Jablonka’s paper Dougherty and Hamilton argued that the postulation of a mechanism of limited associative learning was unnecessary and instead, we should be looking for “a difference in the kind or environmental regularities that can influence behaviour” (Dialogue on Learning p. 50).

            When Jablonka pointed out that we need something in different kinds of organisms to explain how they interpreted the world. They replied when you start to identify different parts of the brain in terms of functions, you lose sight of environmental-behaviour relations (ibid p52). At this point in the discussion Steven Hayes who is the founder and lead figure in Contextual Behavioural Science discussed the concept of taste aversion in rats an argued that most experts in the field explain this as a kind of temporal distortion of classical conditioning. And Hayes notes the following:

“I would be surprised, Mike, if you think it was a bad thing to look at the underlying neurobiology of taste aversion, given this extraordinary distortion of temporal parameters.” (ibid p. 53)

The reply that Hayes gets makes it clear that the contextual behavioural scientists are only interested in the neurobiology of taste aversion to the extent that it gives prediction and control of the organism in particular contexts. It is unclear whether what precisely their views on neurological mechanisms in the brain is other than the fact they are only interested in such postulations to the extent to which they help us predict and control the organism and his environment.

            One can see from the above discussion that the debate as to whether it is advisable to postulate hypothetical mechanisms to explain the behaviour of organisms is still a live issue and isn’t limited to disagreements on the philosophy of science fifty years ago. It is fair to say that the position adopted by Quine and Jablonka would still be the mainstream position adopted by the scientific community. And those working in the radical behaviourist or CBS positions are in the minority. But obviously a philosophical disagreement cannot be decided by majority rules. And the methodology adopted by CBS while not mainstream hasn’t stopped them achieving notable success achieving experimental understanding in relation to rule-following, stimulus equivalence and relations of coordination etc. It is an open empirical question as to whether they could have achieved these results adapting a more mechanistic philosophical framework.


[1]  B.F. Skinner: A case history in the scientific method 1956.

[2] Quine is speaking of any physical entities disposition e.g., the disposition of salt to dissolve when in water. He thinks these can be cashed out in terms of some hypothetical physical states. Here we will limit our attention to dispositions of living organisms to behave in certain ways in certain circumstances.

[3] Skinner obviously wouldn’t parse the Pigeons behaviour in the above manner.

[4] Though Quine’s positions do bear some similarities to pre-Skinnerian behaviourists such as Pavlov and Hull.

[5] This paper was printed in Wilson and Hayes (eds), ‘Evolution and Contextual Behavioural Science’

[6] Henceforth Contextual Behavioural Science will be referred to as CBS.

[7] O Keefe’s work on place cell’s role in the cognitive maps won him the Nobel Prize in (2014).

Quine, Hume, and Contextual Behavioural Science.

Introduction

In this blogpost I will discuss a 2001 paper by Wilson et al ‘Hume’s psychology contemporary learning theory and the problem of knowledge amplification’. The primary claim of their paper was that Hume’s speculations about how we acquire our theory of the world can be updated and made more precise using evidence from contemporary behavioural science. A barrier to using behavioural science to update Hume’s philosophy was that behavioural principles such as Operant and Classical Conditioning are shared by most living creatures and all mammals, so they don’t give us an obvious explication of human specific capacities. Wilson et al argue that the discovery of relation frames; in particular, the human specific capacity to achieve stimulus equivalence, as well as relations of hierarchy, coordination etc helps us explicate the higher reaches of human cognition, such as our capacity for verbal behaviour.

I will argue that while their project shares much in common with Quine’s earlier attempt to naturalize our epistemology there are some differences between the two projects. In particular, the pragmatist philosophy which underlies the contextual behavioural science is at odds with Quine’s more mechanistic view. Quine thinks of behaviour as evidence to be used to discover underlying mechanisms while Contextual Behavioural Scientists are primarily concerned with whole organism environmental interactions and deriving techniques to achieve prediction and control over such organisms.

Finally, I will argue that Contextual Behavioural Science offers us a more complete account of our capacity to acquire verbal behaviour than Quine managed and hence is a more complete account of how we go from stimulus to science than Quine achieved.

                 Causation, Induction and Pecking Pigeons

“There is nothing more basic to thought and language than our sense of similarity; our sorting of things into kinds. The usual general term, whether a common noun or a verb  or an adjective, owes its generality to some resemblance among the things referred to. Indeed, learning to use a word depends on a double resemblance: first, a resemblance between the present circumstances and past circumstances in which the word was used, and second, a phonetic resemblance between the present utterance of the word and past utterances of it. And every reasonable expectation depends on resemblance of circumstances, together with our tendency to expect similar causes to have similar effects. (Quine: Natural Kinds pp 116-117)

In their 2001 paper Hume’s psychology contemporary learning theory and the problem of knowledge amplification’ Wilson et all’s attempted to update Hume’s epistemology with results from contemporary behavioural science. Hume had famously parsed the laws of association in terms of resemblance, contiguity in space and time, and cause and effect. Wilson et al redescribed Hume’s three criteria using traditional behavioural science. So, for example, they explained resemblance in terms of stimulus generalization. Stimulus generalization is where an organism under stimulus control also responds to stimulus that bears a formal resemblance to the stimulus. And they gave an example of a Pigeon trained to peck under the stimulus of a red light and how scientists could establish a curve in the Pigeons behaviour by altering the stimulus (fading from a red light to a yellow light). Quine had made a similar argument to this in his The Roots of Reference.

Reception is flagrantly physical. But perception also, for all its mentalistic overtones, is accessible to behavioural criteria. It shows itself in the conditioning of responses. Thus suppose we provide an animal with a screen to look at and a lever to press. He finds that the pressed lever brings a pellet of food when the screen shows a circular stripe, and it brings a shock when the screen shows merely four spots spaced in a semicircular arc. Now we present him with those same four spots, arranged as before, but supplemented with three more to suggest the complementary semicircle. If the animal presses the lever, he may be said to have perceived the circular Gestalt rather than the component spots.” (The Roots of Reference p. 4)

One key difference between Quine’s argument and Wilson et al is that Quine used the behavioural evidence to speculate on the perceptual experience of the organism while Wilson et al eschewed this speculation. This is in keeping with differences in the philosophy of Quine and those of a Contextual Behavioural Science approach. Despite some passages which indicate otherwise; Quine is mechanist whose priority is in explaining behaviour in terms of physiological mechanisms. This mechanistic philosophy puts him at odds with the pragmatism of contextual behavioural science.

            For both Quine and the Contextual Behavioural Scientist stimulus generalization will count as a behavioural criterion for resemblance. When it comes to contiguity in space and time the Contextualist Behavioural Scientist speaks instead of contingencies. So, they are not concerned merely with close temporal paring, rather they are interested in “the relative likelihood of one event given the other, and that same event given the lack of the other” (Wilson et al. p.9).  They do note that contiguity will predict a contingency, and for most purposes stimuli which are nearby in time will be most psychologically salient (ibid p. 9). A 0.5 second interval between the onset of a conditioned stimulus and the onset of an unconditioned stimulus has been empirically shown to be optimal in for classical conditioning (ibid p.9). If stimuli are separated by time and distance conditioning doesn’t typically occur (ibid p.9).

            While Quine uses reinforcement throughout his texts, he doesn’t explicate the type of schedules which are useful for classical or operant conditioning to occur. Some schedules of reinforcement e.g., fixed interval or variable interval schedules indicate the temporal spreads which are most successful in producing conditioning. Such schedules would be relevant to giving a behavioural slant on contiguity in time. But Quine is silent on the issue[1].

            Presumably Quine was assuming that reinforcement occurred immediately after the behaviour. But as we know from Skinner’s work different schedules of reinforcement have different conditioning patterns. Quine’s silence on what schedules of reinforcement are involved in acquiring different skills makes it difficult to evaluate his speculations for truth value. Furthermore, unlike the Contextual Behavioural Scientists he has no method of replacing contiguity with contingencies.  

            Hume’s explains causation by appealing to three principles (1) Contiguity, (2) Succession, (3) Constant Conjunction. He illustrates with his famous billiard ball example. If one billiard ball hits another the other ball moves. This movement involves both balls being contiguous in space and time and one ball hitting the second ball prior to the second ball moving. But Hume notes that in this case all we can say is that one event followed another. To claim that the event caused the other event we need a constant conjunction, e.g., events of type A are constantly followed by events of type B. Wilson et all parse the idea of constant conjunction in terms of similarity “we expect similar effects from similar causes” (ibid p.10).

            Wilson et all’s characterisation isn’t quite accurate of Hume’s views. Consider the billiard ball example. Experience looking at billiards shows us that when one ball hits the other ball the second ball tends to move. Hume would parse this as constant conjunction of event of type A preceding event of type B. Whereas Wilson et all would conceive of it as when causes similar to A (one billiard ball hitting the other billiard ball), occur effects similar to B (the second billiard ball moves) occur.

            Nonetheless, Wilson et al are correct we cannot explain the constant conjunction of different classes of events without being able to categorize events as similar and dissimilar to each other[2]. And their stimulus generalization is a good behavioural indicator of how once an organisms’ behaviour becomes under stimulus control, we can extrapolate their similarity structures. And how once we switch from looking for contingencies of reinforcement instead of contiguity, we can speak of the probability of one event of kind x following another event of kind y. So, we have a behavioural account of some of the key features of our concept of cause.

Human Specific Capacities

                  They correctly note that one of the difficulties with the account provided in terms of learning theory is that these learning theoretical tools: stimulus generalization, operant conditioning, classical conditioning etc occur in all mammals. But humans have capacities which go beyond all-other animals. So, they argue we may need new principles to explain uniquely human cognitive capacities. They argue that they can explain this special sauce which only humans possess in terms of Stimulus Equivalence and Relational Frame Theory:

       To reiterate, a set of conditional discriminations may be trained wherein the two relations, given A”, pick B” and given A”, pick C” are established by direct reinforcement. In such a case a nonhuman has learned and can respond selectively to precisely these two directly trained relations. A verbally competent human, on the other hand, can respond selectively to trials encompassing A to B relations, B to A relations, A to C relations, C to A relations, B to C relations, and finally C to B relations. From an economic perspective, training two relations to a nonhuman generates two potential relational responses; whereas training two relations to a human generates six (two directly trained, and four derived). (Wilson et al p.13).

After their discussion of human specific capacity in terms of “equivalence of class” they go on to discuss the human specific capacity of “transfer of function”. This capacity has interesting psychological consequences. So, if A1 is paired with an electric shock sufficiently to establish it as an aversive stimulus, then B1 will also work as an aversive stimulus. And if the equivalence relations have been established through multi-exemplar training, then these relations will also be subject to a transfer of function.

“Thus, given A} B training and A}C training, and with C given an aversive function, a human would learn to avoid A, B, and C, whereas a nonverbal organism would require three separate conditioning procedures one for each of the A, B, and C stimuli.” (Ibid p.14)

They also note that while they have spoken of equivalence functions there are also other relational frames such as hierarchy, coordination, oppositeness, greater/smaller than, etc. Another key feature which they note is that these frames are learned through contextual cues (ibid p. 14). The key point is these experimentally derived capacities are unique to humans. Despite hundreds of experiments on dozens of non-human animals Contextual Behavioural Scientists have yet to discover the capacity of any non-human to engage in relational frames. This indicates that there is an innate component to the capacity.

            While there is there an incredible amount of behavioural evidence to support the existence of relational frames. And these frames are suggestive for being the secret sauce behind linguistic productivity. There is as of yet very little engagement with generative grammarians to construct mathematical models to see if the types of relational frames discovered can be used to construct the mathematical structures discovered in linguistics. Nonetheless, their experimental studies do take us a long way from Quine’s model of how we acquire our language and theory of the world. Quine vaguely speculated things like similarity quality spaces, and a capacity for analogical synthesis which we use to associate sentences with sentences. But he provided no details on how this was done.


[1] Contiguity in space and time doesn’t always produce conditioning. Wilson et al. discuss the case of taste aversion in rats where through genetic changes the temporal parameters in classical conditioning were modified. This demonstrates that Quine isn’t justified in simply ignoring evidence from schedules of reinforcement when he is speculating.

[2] Quine made a similar point in his postulation of an innate prelinguistic quality space in his Word and Object.

Intersectionality and Intellectual Disability

In this blogpost I will discuss social locations and how social locations effect our experiences in the world. The focus will be on the set of social locations at the intersection of intellectual disability, being non-verbal, and coming from a family from a disadvantaged background. Social locations can be thought of as a map with intersecting points which result in the relative advantages and disadvantages, we experience as we negotiate our world. The interactions between our various social locations and how these interactions shape our life best understood in the context of intersectionality. Olena Hankivsky defines Intersectionality as follows:

“Intersectionality promotes an understanding of human beings as shaped by the interaction of different social locations (e.g., ‘race’/ethnicity, indigeneity, gender, class, sexuality, geography, age, disability/ability, migration, status, religion). These interactions occur within a context of connected systems and structures of power (Laws, Policies, state governments and other political and economic unions, religious institutions, media). Through such processes, interdependent forms of privilege and oppression shaped by colonialism, imperialism, racism, homophobia, ableism and patriarchy are created” (Hankivsky: Intersectionality 101. p.2)

 There are an incredible number of intersecting levels of disadvantage which can be experienced by a non-verbal person with an intellectual disability. I this blogpost I will explore the unique nature of these disadvantages in comparison to other disadvantaged groups. The primary focus will be on the nature of these disadvantages and techniques which can be used to overcome the disadvantages. A key focus will be on the notion of recognition and how recognition plays a large role in any distribution of funds. I will discuss current techniques which are being used which help advocate for and increase recognition for people with an intellectual disability and argues that this increase in recognition will increase the likelihood of fair distributions of funds, and that this fairer distribution will result intersectional disadvantages becoming less severe.

                   Intersecting Sets: Intersectionality and Intellectual disability

             Having a disability of any kind can result in disadvantages in accessing various aspects of society. Having an intellectual disability can result in further disadvantages; because this can result in a person having a diminished capacity to articulate and justify ones wants and needs. A non-verbal person with an intellectual disability has even further disadvantages because they cannot even articulate their needs and are reliant on others to advocate for them in society. Or at the very least are reliant on the society they are living in valuing them and hence funding research and distribution of augmentative communication devices. So, in this situation you have interconnected sets of potential disadvantages {Disability {Intellectual Disability {Non-Verbal}}}.

            A person in this state of affairs is reliant on a combination of legislation e.g., Assisted Decision Making Act, Advocacy from Family members, and state sponsored agencies such as Tusla. But there are further lairs of disadvantage that can affect a person. A non-verbal person with an intellectual disability who is put into care because their family can no longer look after him is in an even more precarious situation. In some situations, people with an intellectual disability are put in care because their parents may not have the financial resources or educational capacity to adequately care for them.

            In this situation you have a person who with a {disability {Intellectual Disability { non-verbal { working class { advocates who are unclear about structural entitlements. }}}}}. These interconnected sets of disadvantages impinge on and interact with each other. Having an intellectual disability and being non-verbal impinges dramatically on one’s ability to advocate for oneself, but if your primary advocates have poor educational and financial resources then this can lead to greater difficulties for to achieving what you want.

            The person in this situation is doubly disadvantaged. If a person is disabled, say is in a wheelchair, and lives in a society which has limited wheelchair access, they can conceptualize the difficulty and join advocacy groups, to push for change. Similar situations apply to a person of colour conceptualising and fighting racism and white privilege. Or a Gay person living in a society which is homophobic. But our non-verbal person with an intellectual disability is not in the same situation. It would be extremely difficult to explain to this person that his parents are disadvantaged and would lack the conceptual resources to advocate on his behalf in the area. Furthermore, it would be difficult to explain to him the nature of these resources, the economic factors, and legal factors that go into decisions of this nature. In this country it is policy that providers should explain these factors to service users under their care; and this is typically catered for by Speech and Language Therapists designing easy to read tools that carers can use to try and help the service users understand their rights. However, these easy read tools dramatically underestimate the difficulty of explaining abstract concepts in a non-verbal manner using pictures (Wittgenstein 1951).

            People with an intellectual disability typically have their resources controlled by outside forces (Watchman 2018). Not even knowing what factors are impinging on your wellbeing, not knowing whether you are being given a fair distribution of goods for your daily living etc. In this situation a person could be oppressed without having any conception that they are being oppressed. Their family acting as advocates may not have a full conception of the nature of such oppression. Leaving the vulnerable non-verbal person acting in a world around him with no conception of the nature of this world and his entitlements.

            There are some factors which can be useful to help people in this situation. In put from Speech and Language to help improve functional communication, augmentative communication techniques such as Lamh, PECS, Objects of Reference etc. Can give people some capacity to represent themselves and their interests. But these linguistic tools are more useful for people with practical engagement with one’s environment and aren’t tools of sufficient grammatical or conceptual power to understand and argue for ones ‘rights’, ‘obligations’ etc.

            In such cases it will fall to employees working in an organisation to advocate on behalf of the service users living in their homes. This advocacy will be constrained by legal regulations provided by external organisations such as Hiqa. Staff will have to ensure that various regulations are met such as prudent person-centred finances, regular service user meetings, and keyworker meetings, staff training is sufficient to provide care for the service users etc. Once these regulations are in place and Hiqa pass the house on their twice a year inspection then it is generally accepted that the service users have been sufficiently advocated for.

            However, we see in our daily lives that despite laws in relation to racism, sexism etc. inequality still occurs in relation to how people are treated in their daily lives. Is it not likely that similar things could happen to service users whose houses are passed by Hiqa as sufficiently well regulated? Are there inequalities between service users within an organisation who come from affluent families who are educated and who know how to use the system to achieve the best outcomes for their child, and service users whose families are poor and uneducated. It isn’t implausible that organisations will prioritise the needs of service users whose families have the capacity and the knowledge to bring litigation against the organisation and those who do not. It is possible for an organisation to meet the minimal regulatory needs of a service user but for the distribution between service users to be unequal.

            If this did indeed occur, it would be an unjust situation. You would have two sets of service users with a similar demographic: intellectual disability, non-verbal, etc. But one group would have more advantages because of the economic and political profile of their family. This would be an unjust situation and a situation the service user would be unaware of and even if they were aware they would not have the conceptual resources to fight it.

            Now a possible avenue would be for the employees within individual houses to fight the disparity. But in this situation, one would be in a state of affairs where staff or middle management would be required to make accusations of injustice against senior management and the service provider. This could be potentially a dangerous situation for staff to be in and it is not a reliable system to expect justice to arrive from staff fighting systems of power in the organisations the work in.

            We can see a three-pronged approach to try and advocate for service users who cannot advocate for themselves; (1) ensure that the service user needs are met in a person-centred manner according to policies set by Hiqa, (2) Ensuring that service users goods are distributed to all service users in the service in an equitable manner.  This involves ensuring that one group do not benefit in a manner that is disproportionate to the benefits given to the other group. (3) Ensure that service user rights are met in the same way as members of the general public’s rights are met.

            A danger in activism is that we sometimes end up erasing the people who are being advocated for. Thus, when it comes to an area such as gay rights, we want gay people at the centre of the conversation speaking about their experiences and how they feel society treats them. While CIS het people can be allies in this process, we do not want them at the centre of the process leading the way on a subject matter which they have no direct experience of. Yet in the case of non-verbal people with an intellectual disability it would appear to be the advocates who are centre stage not the people being advocated for.

The language of person-centredness is important and when adopting this philosophy, one is taking a first steps towards putting the non-verbal person with an intellectual disability at the centre of the conversation. But when it comes to more abstract concepts such as parity of economic distribution; or an issue such as having the right to go for a walk in a beech more to 5 Kilometres away from your home versus the responsibility to not spread an infectious disease during a pandemic; issues become more complex. Despite the use of things like storyboards, PECS, easy to read pamphlets on human rights etc. It is extremely difficult to try and explicate these concepts to a non-verbal person with an intellectual disability.

However, despite the difficulties we must continue to try and put in place techniques which can help the service users advocate on their own behalf. Philosopher Nancy Fraizer has noted that as a matter of empirical fact redistribution and recognition go hand in hand (Fraser, N. 2001 p.87). Service user councils are a tool which can work to give service users a voice in the shaping the role of the organisation which they live in. As I mentioned earlier it is difficult for non-verbal people to express their wishes in these councils but with augmentative communication devices it is not impossible. Furthermore, they can partake in voting for representatives and the representative will at least be a person with an intellectual disability who has direct experience of being a service user in a particular organisation. Having representatives within these organisations is a way of increasing recognition of the people with an intellectual disability. With recognition that service users can advocate on their own behalf arguments for fairer redistribution become more likely.

While having representation which leads to recognition within the organisation is important to increase recognition within the wider community. Policies in Ireland such as the new directions policy with its foundation of person-centeredness informing policies in relation to community inclusion, a right to formal education and training, right to vocational training, right to meaningful social roles etc. Are important tools in helping people with an intellectual disability access their own community and operate as valued members of society.

With being in the community whether working in a job or studying; the person with an intellectual disability becomes a recognised member of his own community. Prior to de-congregation service users were hidden away from the general public and this resulted in a state of affairs where they were not given recognition as members of our community. And as Fraizer noted when there is no recognition there will be no major push for redistribution of funds to increase the service user’s quality of life.

However, with the person-centred push to get people out into the community things are much different. The general public see on a daily basis the value people with an intellectual disability whether verbal or non-verbal can provide for the community and with this recognition it becomes an easier job to advocate for increasing funding for various different services located within the wider community.

                                   Conclusion

I have here explored people who are non-verbal and have an intellectual disability and discussed their situation from the point of view of intersectionality. The blog detailed the nested threads of disadvantage that can occur when a person is disabled, has an intellectual disability, is non-verbal and comes from a family with a disadvantaged socio-economic background. Techniques which could be used to help people in this scenario were discussed, including legislation, external auditors, advocates etc. Though despite these techniques the author argued that there is still a possibility inequal distribution of finances. To minimize the likelihood of this happening I argued using the work of philosopher Nancy Frazer that increased recognition will lead to a greater likelihood fairer distribution of funds. An outlined some concepts that serve to increase recognition for non-verbal people with an intellectual disability such as community inclusion, service user councils etc.

                                Bibliography

Fraser, N. (2001) ‘Recognition Without Ethics?’ Theory Culture and Society. 18 (2-3) 21-42

Olena, H. (2014) Intersectionality 101. The Institute for Intersectionality Research and Policy, SFU.

Watchman, K. (2018) “The Intersectionality of Intellectual disability and ageing.” Ageing, Diversity and Equality: Social Justice Perspectives. Routledge.

Wittgenstein, L. (1951) The Philosophical Investigations. Routledge.